The Inaugural Scalia Lecture | Judge Frank Easterbrook: Interpreting the Unwritten Constitution

Video Statistics and Information

Video
Captions Word Cloud
Reddit Comments
Captions
DEAN MINOW: Good afternoon. As Dean of the Harvard Law School, I have just distinct joy to welcome you all here to this inaugural Justice Antonin Scalia lecture. Established in 2013, this is a brand new lecture series. This is the first of the brand new lecture series. And you are here. This lecture series was established to promote and advance understanding of the founding principles and the core doctrines of the United States Constitution. Devoted to public service and to thinking, the brilliant Justice Scalia-- brilliant lawyer, brilliant professor, brilliant judge, brilliant justice-- so powerfully exemplifies the purposes behind this lecture series. With his eloquence, cogency, wisdom, humor, he has advanced the principles of justice and the foundational ideas of our Constitution. How honored we are that we at his alma mater are the recipients of a donor who prefers to remain non-anonymous in choosing to honor Justice Scalia and to advance knowledge and teaching with lectures in his honor. We are charged to find scholars or figures of high distinction who do their work, research, writings, and teaching elucidate the principles of the American founding. The fields can include political science, philosophy, religion, law, related disciplines. We are thrilled that Justice Scalia, Mrs. Scalia, and members of the family and friends are here with us today as we launch the significant series. Please join me in saluting them. [APPLAUSE] And how thrilled we are that our inaugural Justice Antonin Scalia lecturer is Judge Frank Easterbrook. He shares with the lecture's namesake distinguished public service and academic accomplishment. But I think he's the only one who carried a briefcase in second grade, which I have on good authority is the fact. [LAUGHTER] After graduation from the University of Chicago Law School, he served as a law clerk to Judge Campbell of the United States Court of Appeals for the First Circuit. He then worked at the office of Solicitor General, first as an assistant, then as Deputy Solicitor General for the United States. And one of the distinctive features of his work as a professor and as a judge is his clarity. You can take any complicated problem and he gets to the heart of it. He also is well known with bringing economic analysis to law. He's one of the most prolific judges of his generation. His clear writing and his legalist approach and, oh yes, the Chicago connection, make this particularly a wonderful connection between Justice Scalia and Judge Easterbrook. And in fact, the brilliance of these two men really, I think, ignites even this dark evening sky. Please join me in thanking Judge Easterbrook for taking on this role and for setting the standard so high that I think we're going to have a difficult time finding others to live up to this standard. And join me in welcoming him and get ready with your questions because there is no one who asks tougher questions from the bench. So get ready. Please, Judge Easterbrook. [APPLAUSE] JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Thank you, dean. When Dean Minow asked me to deliver the inaugural Scalia lecture, I was pleased to have the opportunity to honor my friend and colleague, Justice Scalia. Many of you know that we were both on the faculty of the University of Chicago until his appointment to the DC Circuit. We shared intellectual interests in administrative and antitrust law. In his role as editor of Regulation Magazine-- maybe he's even forgotten about that-- he prompted me to write some short pieces about those subjects. The year after his judicial appointment and departure to DC, I moved to the Seventh Circuit. But despite distance, we've maintained our friendship. Most of you do not know that I first met Nino Scalia in the conference room of Attorney General Levi during the Ford Administration, when I was an assistant to Solicitor General Bork and he was the Assistant Attorney General for the Office of Legal Counsel. This means that I've known Nino for almost 40 years. Edward Levi persuaded both of us to join the faculty at Chicago, but our joint project at the Department of Justice had little to do with the Legal Academy. President Eisenhower had instructed federal agents to open mail to and from the Soviet Union in order to catch spies. There was no statutory basis for this program, and a federal statute made mail-opening a felony. Whether this program produced any useful intelligence is open to doubt, but like many federal programs, it continued, despite the lack of results. [LAUGHTER] And despite intervening events, such as a 1972 decision by the Supreme Court, that even searches justified by National Security usually require warrants when executed within our borders. None of Eisenhower's successors as president had even heard about this program, which came to light during President Ford's tenure. He asked the Department of Justice to look into the matter. And Attorney General Levi turned to his most trusted advisers, including Solicitor General Bork and Assistant Attorney General Scalia, who foolishly or otherwise asked some of their aides to participate. President Ford told the snoops to desist. Attorney General Levi had to decide whether to prosecute. The statute was clear, but so was President Eisenhower's instruction, which predated the Supreme Court's 1972 decision. The working group decided that it would be unjust to prosecute people who in good faith had implemented this presidential order. The group also decided to issue a report explaining this decision and stating that if mails should be opened again in the future, prosecutions would follow, no matter who gave the order. The report described the program of the statute it violated. It discussed whether the President, who the Constitution says must take care that the laws be faithfully executed, could direct that laws be violated. It said almost never, with the almost reflecting Justice Jackson's observations that the Constitution is not a suicide pact and this nation's history, including President Lincoln's decision that some laws, and at least one judicial order, could not be followed if the nation were to be saved. President Eisenhower's program was not in that category, however. On the other side was the right of the citizens to confidentiality of their mail communications, which was protected not only by statute but also by the First Amendment. Solicitor General Bork signed off on the report's conclusions and its reasoning. Attorney General Levi did too. Assistant Attorney General Scalia was content with the non-prosecution decision but not with the rest of the report. He sat back in his chair, looked up, and said, you're making it all up. You're just making it all up. He was right, of course. The legal analysis in the report was being made up because the problem was novel, but Attorney General Levi thought it proper to articulate his thinking. When making it up, the Department of Justice was explaining its own conduct and constraining no one, not even later attorney's general. But when judges make it up, they purport to bind other people-- presidents, legislators, attorney's general, states, private parties. The need to have a basis for a decision that forces strangers to change their conduct is a theme of Justice Scalia's jurisprudence. And usually a judge must point to an authoritative text in order to impose such a duty. Making it all up is out of the question for a judge. Many judicial decisions proclaim that making it up just won't do for government in general. When presidents or legislatures or agencies make it up, judges tend to issue injunctions and intone that in the United States, all assertions of powered and unformally adopted texts. So when President Truman seized the steel mills to keep supplies flowing during the Korean War, the justices held that even a wartime commander-in-chief lacks authority to do this unless legislation grants that power. When Congress decided that administrative agencies had run amuck and must be checked by a rule that a single house of Congress could disapprove the excesses, the justices replied that no matter how beneficial the check might be, it flunks the Constitution's bicameralism requirement. And just last term, the Supreme Court delivered the same message to the EPA, reminding the agency that it acts under delegated powers and must ground its decisions in them, rather than in its views of wise policy. To quote from the utility air decision, "An agency has no power to tailor legislation to bureaucratic policy goals by rewriting unambiguous statutory terms. Agencies exercise discretion only in the interstices created by statutory silence or ambiguity." Well, if presidents, agencies, and legislatures all must rely on authoritative texts, and if arguments based on wise policy are no substitute for a written delegation, that statement must be true of our third branch as well. Making it all up is forbidden to everyone and especially to judges, whose authority depends on old text rather than recent election. Tenure freeze judges from current opinion, the better to enforce old decisions. But like the force, tenure has a dark side. [LAUGHTER] In freeing judges from popular opinion, it can free judges from law as well. The dark side of tenure is self-indulgence. It's therefore no surprise that judges see all around them on written grants of power to the judiciary unwritten grants that if asserted by other branches of government would be laughed at and enjoined. Many in the legal academy celebrate those decisions, for they often adopt policies that could not be enacted easily, if at all, by persons who need the electorate's approbation on the election day. You may have thought from my title, "Interpreting the Unwritten Constitution," that I am going to talk about these decisions. I'm not. By the "unwritten Constitution," I don't mean Bruce Ackerman's ghostly constitutional conventions that ratify invisible amendments. Or Akhil Amar's unwritten fundamental rights that supplement the ones adopted by the people. Or David Strauss's common law constitution in which judges continually adopt incremental improvements that bind the other branches, but somehow never constrain the judiciary. And those are only three recent academic treatments. I've omitted proposals by the faculty of this law school. [LAUGHTER] I have in mind a different flavor of unwritten constitution, the kind originalists approve. Justice Scalia and I are in that category and must explain how we can espouse doctrines that do not appear in the Constitution's text. The principal on written doctrine is judicial review itself. Marbury against Madison, decided in 1803, is the foundation for modern judicial authority, but it's just an inference from constitutional structure. The Constitution doesn't have a judicial review clause. That has profound implications for the nature and limits of judicial authority. And here are a few more unwritten doctrines-- intergovernmental tax immunities, sovereign immunity, limits on federal coercion of the states in their sovereign capacity. For example, Congress can't demand that state legislatures pass laws, the assignment of Foreign Affairs to the President, the equal footing doctrine under which all states have the same status, no matter when and how they join the union, the rule of lenity for interpreting criminal statutes which rests on the view that common law crimes are constitutionally forbidden. Are these unwritten doctrines illegitimate? Legitimate? If they are legitimate, does the reasoning that makes them legitimate have implications about how much those doctrines may be called on to do? Those are my topics today. I want to talk about four of the doctrines-- judicial review, tax immunities, the ban on commandeering the states, and sovereign immunity. Our time is short and the history of these doctrines long, so I must omit much more than I can cover. But in a nutshell, my thesis is that all of these doctrines are legitimate. But the reasoning that makes them legitimate imposes limits on what judges can do in their name and, in particular, calls for modifications to the commandeering and sovereign immunity doctrines in order to bring them in line with the modern tax immunity doctrine. But I'm sure all of you need a little refresher on the tax immunity doctrine. Before we do that, though, and to see where I'm going and how I'm going to get there, I need to start with judicial review. Marbury's major premise is that the Constitution is law, the supreme law, binding on all parts of the government, and sufficiently clear to be enforceable as law. Chief Justice Marshall gives the ex post facto clause as an example and asks rhetorically whether in case of a clear conflict a judge applies the retrospective criminal law. He observes that the Constitution contains a hierarchy, but it's supreme over statutes and treaties. Finally, Marshall observes that every public official owes a duty by virtue of an oath, if not the written nature of the document, to follow the Supreme law in the event of conflict. Written instruments are meant to have bite, and our Constitution not only is written, but also establishes a system of generally limited government. If there are limits, there are boundaries. Otherwise, the government's not limited after all. On this understanding, the writing itself means the power exists only if delegated. And if authority depends on delegation, everyone, including judges, must enforce the limits. It's not a claim of judicial supremacy. It is a claim of every official's obligation under the Constitution. Now there are problems in Chief Justice Marshall's explanation. It begs a critical question-- why most political actors pay any more attention to the judge's decision than the judges paid to the legislatures? Chief Justice Marshall's implicit answer is that the constitutional hierarchy binds everyone and simply to demonstrate the argument for the meaning of the Constitution is to ensure acquiescence. Congress and the President follow the court because the same syllogism that drives the court's decision drives everyone else's too. That is, there were understandable rules, they were laid down in the past, they govern us still. To have identified the rule is to identify the reason why all must obey. The Supreme Court's decision about the content of the rule prevails because the definition of a rule is one that's given to all alike. And judicial review under Marbury, therefore, is a search for rules. If the age or generality of a text frustrates the discovery of a rule, then it also defeats a claim of judicial power. When the living much chart their own course, the questions outside the domain of judicial review. You can't have a view that denies the power of the past to rule today's state of affairs, yet asserts that Article III alone from the past still binds us. Judicial review depends on the belief that decisions taken long ago are authoritative today. The judge's duty, Hamilton said in "Federalist Number 78," is to declare all acts contrary to the manifest tenure of the Constitution void. This assumes that the document has a manifest tenure. We broke from England, after all, by having written rules and therefore enforcement, instead of having only practices and consensus. One important implication of this understanding is when the framers did not create a rule, when the issue was novel, or when the original interpretive community can't be recovered reliably, we have neither judicial review nor the feared dead hand, but democracy. That is the core of the Constitution. Modern issues are decided by elected representatives. Recovering the original meaning is much harder for us than it was for Chief Justice Marshall. Finding rules in constitutional structure depends on sure knowledge of how those living in the late 18th century thought about law. Marshall and his contemporaries lived in that interpretive community. We do not. This is a fundamental point in linguistics, made by Wittgenstein and elaborated by others. A text doesn't contain any rule beyond those points actively addressed and resolved by the authors and understood by those who received the text. But modern debates may deal with issues that were unimaginable two centuries ago. Even when we know that a decision has been made, we may be unable to recover it reliably. Consider whether the Constitution gives Congress the power to regulate medical marijuana. There may have been a real decision in 1787 about the meaning of commerce among the several states, but that depends on context. Not simply the context of the word, but the context of the times. Let's Wittgenstein again. Words have meaning only in the context of an interpretive community, what judges and legal scholars these days call original public meaning. When that community dies, the meaning of words can be lost. That's why we needed a Rosetta Stone to decipher hieroglyphics and why we still can't decipher Linear A, the Minoan script. William Winslow Crosskey tried to reconstruct the original interpretive community for the commerce clause. He concluded, based on his reading of 18th century newspapers and pamphlets, that commerce among the states means all commerce that occurs in any state. Transporter shipments are unnecessary. Charles Fairman of this law school read the same sources and reached a more conventional conclusion. Who's right? Judges can't be historians. There isn't enough time. And more importantly, neither Crosskey nor Fairman nor any living judge can read 18th century press clippings the same way the founding generation would have read them. The political and linguistic culture has changed so thoroughly that recovery of the earlier interpretive community may not be possible. And that's why we need a second theory of judicial review. And Chief Justice Marshall supplied that too, along with the one he gave us in Marbury. The second theory is in McCulloch against Maryland-- a case that, by the way, devised the intergovernmental tax immunity doctrine that I am luring you toward. [LAUGHTER] But I want to start with the portion of McCulloch that explains why Congress has the power to create a bank of the United States-- for modern ears, think Federal Reserve-- even though banking isn't among the national government's enumerated powers. When James Madison first considered the bank's constitutional status, while he was in the House of Representatives where he voted against it, he thought it beyond the new national government's powers. On second take, Madison, by then the President, signed the bill establishing the Second Bank of the United States. He said that no one who had had a hand in creating this nation was so foolish as to think that all the interesting decisions are encoded in the original text. The decision was to create a federal republic and let the people work out through their representatives the problems of time still to come. Madison believed that the ways in which the first few generations dealt with these ambiguities would settle their meaning. It follows that a practice adopted early in our history must still be settled. Otherwise, we're throwing out both the linguistic community and the original mechanism for dispute resolution. And then the approach in Marbury couldn't justify any judicial role. When the bank came to the Supreme Court in McCulloch, the justices approved Madison's process of resolving ambiguities. The bank's proponents pointed to two things-- sorry, the bank's opponents pointed to two things. The Constitution creates limited federal powers, and nothing authorizes the national government to create financial intermediaries. To charter a bank, Congress therefore needed to rely on the power to enact laws necessary and proper to put the other powers into effect. But how could the bank be necessary? The nation could survive without a central bank. It did so between 1810 and 1816, and it would again between 1836 and 1913. By taking "necessary" strictly, the court could have set itself up as a potent political force reviewing the wisdom of wars. The court resisted. And I want to quote at some length from Chief Justice Marshall. "Among the enumerated powers, we do not find that of establishing a bank or creating a corporation. But there's no phrase in the instrument which, like the Articles of Confederation, excludes incidental or implied powers, and which requires that everything granted shall be expressly and minutely described. A constitution to contain an accurate detail of all the subdivisions of which its great powers will admit, and of all the means by which they may be carried into execution, would partake of the prolixity of a legal code, and could scarcely be embraced by the human mind. It would probably never be understood by the public. Its nature therefore requires that only the great outline should be marked, its important objects designated, and minor ingredients which compose those objects be deduced from the nature of the objects themselves. That this idea was entertained by the framers of the American Constitution is not only to be inferred from the nature of the instrument, but from the language. It is also, in some degree, warranted by their having omitted to use any restricted term which might prevent its receiving a fair and just interpretation. In considering this question then, we must never forget that it is a Constitution we are expounding." There's that famous phrase-- "we must never forget that it is a Constitution we are expounding." But now you see its context as a description of legislative latitude. Chief Justice Marshall was explaining why the political branches have authority to act pragmatically while judges do not. He had two theories of constitutional authority. One for Congress, which wields the explicit grants of power, and the other for judges, because while there is a real necessary and proper clause, there is no judicial review clause. Congress and the President drive authority from election and they act under open-ended grants designed for an indefinite future. If the court is to do anything other than bless the product of the political branches, it has to appeal to concrete decisions. Remember the rationale of Marbury. It's a hierarchical rationale, based on the fact that the Constitution has a catalogue of rules, the meaning of which is comprehensible to all those who take the time to study. When judges can reach such a firm conclusion, they may insist that the political outcome yield. That's the originalist constraint. Otherwise, judges must respect politically pragmatic decisions. For what it's worth, I wouldn't lose any sleep over the claim that this leaves us with a wooden constitution or a rule by a dead hand. You have to go back and reread McCulloch. Right? Chief Justice Marshall gave us an approach to an allocation of power over time and among the living in which when there is no definitive decision in the document, we don't have anything dead. We have decision by living majorities. Now, I want to turn from judicial review to the other unwritten doctrines. But you should keep in mind that in dealing with each of these doctrines, I want to ask whether they satisfy the standard of Marbury for allowing judges to countermand elected officials. We now get to the second part of McCulloch, the intergovernmental tax immunity doctrine. How did this case come before the Supreme Court? Maryland tried to tax the Bank of the United States out of existence. The court said no, not because of any snippet of constitutional text forbids state taxation of political instrumentalities, but because the Constitution divides powers between state and federal governments. To the generation living at the end of the 18th century, and for most of the 19th century too, power was absolute when granted and nonexistent otherwise. Congress could create the bank-- that was McCulloch's first holding. And it followed from how the original, interpretive community understood grants of power that only Congress could tax the bank. The power to tax is the power to destroy, Chief Justice Marshall told us, and what a state cannot destroy it cannot tax. This diminished state power, but the court observed that it simultaneously strengthened state power. Because the spheres of sovereignty were divided by the Constitution, states' inability to tax federal instrumentalities meant that the national government couldn't tax state instrumentalities. You can see where this is going. McCulloch and its successor, Osborn against the Bank of the United States, are the progenitors of the anti-commandeering and sovereign immunity doctrines too. Those rules aren't stated in the text. Justice judicial review isn't stated, because they were to the founding generation the inevitable consequence of using texts to divide powers. The meaning of a text is what the interpretive community hears in it at the time of its adoption. And McCulloch, the work of the founding generation, tells us what that is. Chief Justice Marshall gave an example. The Constitution says the Congress may enact laws, but not that it may punish their violation. So the Constitution says that Congress may create a post office, but doesn't say that it may punish theft from the mails. The court observed, however, that a punishment clause would have been odious. Anyone reading a text giving power to create something knows that that carries a power to protect it too. That's just how people in 1787 react to language. For that matter, it's what people today react to language, and so it's part of meaning. State taxes on the bank were equivalent to stealing from the mails. No more need be said. After McCulloch and Osborn, an elaborate structure of tax immunities was erected. States couldn't tax federal agencies or the salaries of federal officers, and especially not the salaries of federal judges. The national government couldn't tax state capitals or the salaries of state employees and so on. I want to tell the story of what happened next through the lens of a different tax immunity doctrine. The approach that led to McCulloch and Osborn also gave us the dormant Commerce Clause. Once again, a grant of power to Congress to regulate commerce was understood to negate any power in the states. And having decided that powers are hermetically separated, the court had to draw a line and create a tax immunity. Power over commerce belongs to Congress. But when does it begin? The court eventually answered-- it begins when goods are put in the containers used for international shipping, and it ends when they're taken out of those containers. This implied a tax immunity, which was announced in Low against Austin in 1872. At the time, a principal source of state revenue was the ad valorem tax on goods in warehouses, before or after international shipment. And the doctrine of Low became known as the original package doctrine. When I was a law student during the early 1970s, this doctrine required more class time than any other in Constitutional Law One. It became frighteningly complex, and it had an interesting sidelight. It gave us Prohibition. The court held that states had the power to ban alcohol, but wine from France or whiskey from Canada could enter in its original package free of state interference. A state might swoop down when you open the shipping crate inside your home, but that would have far exceeded the public's patience. And so as a practical matter, it was impossible for any state to be dry. Congress then exercised its commerce power and authorized the states to stop liquor at their borders. And the Supreme Court held that law invalid because Congress cannot delegate national power to the states. So only a constitutional amendment would serve, and by 1919, the dries had the political clout to adopt the 18th Amendment and ban alcohol everywhere. But for the original package doctrine, national Prohibition would not have existed. Well, you know what happened next. 33 years later, the 21st Amendment repeals the 18th and Section 2 of the 21st Amendment repeals the original package doctrine, but only for liquor. The tax immunity survived and continued to puzzle merchants, tax collectors, and law students until 1976 when Michelin Tire against Wages asked the Supreme Court to decide whether that tissue paper, in which Michelin's radial tires were wrapped for international shipping, was an original package. The justices thought they had never heard a more absurd question in their lives. And they overruled Low and its doctrine. That happened because by 1976, the living interpretive community could no longer think like Chief Justice Marshall did in 1819. McCulloch thought that all power has to be cleanly separated. Long experience, though, had shown that to be impossible. States passed laws, as McCulloch said they could, in spheres outside national power. But any state law, say one taxing real estate, affects interstate commerce. Land is example number one of a state's domain. Real property doesn't cross state boarders. Well, unless the Mississippi changes its course, right? But taxes on real estate affect whether people will cross state borders, on whether people order construction materials from across state borders, and so on. In a market economy, everything effects everything else through the price system. That's why Wickard against Filburn held that Congress can regulate a farmer's ability to bake his own wheat into bread, even though none of the wheat crosses state lines. The full separation that McCulloch envisaged couldn't be maintained unless states were stripped of all powers, and that would violate the original text more surely than any of the doctrines we have been discussing. So what was to be done? In the world of the dormant Commerce Clause, the court began replacing absolute separation with a rule of neutrality. States could regulate domestic commerce, even if that regulation had an effect on interstate commerce, as long as they didn't discriminate against interstate commerce. The court had actually distinguished international from interstate commerce in that way as early as 1868, adopting a nondiscrimination rule that slowly absorbed related doctrines. And it follows from McCulloch that what states can regulate they can tax. That seed was in McCulloch itself, which in an aside said that states could tax the bank's real property at the same rate as privately held property. So tax immunities began shifting from absolute to relative. States acquired the power to tax the salaries of federal employees-- yea, verily, even federal judges. As long as the tax was at the same rate, states applied to their own workers. Federal employees enjoyed vicarious protection. States couldn't tax their salaries-- federal employees' salaries-- without taxing their own employees' salaries. And with the intergovernmental tax immunity shifting to a neutrality rule, the private tax immunity implied by the commerce power had to shift too. That's what Michelin Tire accomplished in 1976. All tax immunity doctrines have now become anti-discrimination rules. I should think that James Madison would smile. This is his preferred method. The modern revisions based on experience do not remove power from either the state or the federal government. They add to each sovereign's authority and leave more space for democracy. And the modern tax neutrality doctrine respects the limits of Marbury. Once the judiciary learns that it can no longer say that the Constitution has an unbending rule against all intergovernmental taxation, judicial authority on Marbury's own terms fades, and the democratic process has to be respected. Now I want to go to our third doctrine, the anti-commandeering doctrine, which says that the national government can't tell states what to do. One modern exemplar is New York against the United States, which holds the national government cannot tell states that they must take title to all radioactive waste created within their borders and deal with the waste themselves. Another is Prince against the United States, which holds that the national government can't offload to states the duty of performing background checks of persons who want to buy guns. These decisions have been much criticized in the law reviews, but the doctrine they instantiate is a sibling of the tax immunity doctrine. And if McCulloch was legitimate, then the anti-commandeering doctrine is legitimate too. Remember that tax immunity is reciprocal. States can't tax the federal government or its bank and the federal government can't tax the states. The doctrine stems from the widely shared assumption that taxation is a form of regulation. What the state can't regulate directly, it can't tax. And the reverse-- what the federal government cannot tax, it cannot regulate. No state could pass a law commanding the FBI to enforce some state law. And it follows from the reciprocity principle that's stated in McCulloch that the national government can't command state police to enforce federal laws or saddle states with tons of radioactive waste-- you could just think of the radioactive waste as a curious form of negative income taxation. But just as a total ban on taxation proved to be unstable, so the anti-commandeering principal hasn't been stable because often states are better off doing things themselves than watching the national government create new bureaucracies. Did anybody really want the national government to create a new bureaucracy to vet applications for gun ownership? The solution has been to allow voluntary state participation in federal programs. I assume that you could hear the quotation marks around voluntary. The 16th Amendment gives Congress the power to tax incomes, which as a practical matter means the power to get tax revenue ahead of the states. Congress preempts the revenue stream, then grants some of that revenue to the states if they agree to do Congress's bidding. It's impossible to imagine an anti-commandeering doctrine without this escape hatch, but also impossible to see how the escape hatch itself can be contained. Consider what happened in National Federation of Independent Business against Sebelius. One part of the Affordable Care Act extends the Medicaid program from certain categories of the poor to everybody making less than 133% of an administratively determined threshold. In other words, the program changes from poor relief to becoming part of a system of universal insurance. The statute nominally gives states a choice whether to accept the extension, but it also provides that if states do not then they lose all federal reimbursements for the original poor relief program. The justices held this coercive by a vote of seven to two, which was a larger margin than either Prince or New York, and a larger margin than the five to four votes in National Federation for the claims arising under the explicit tax-- that is, the commerce clause and the tax clause. The justices agreed more on an unwritten corollary to an unwritten doctrine thaN on the meaning of the Constitution's written clauses. Seven Justices thought, in other words, that Congress had gone too far. Maybe so, but how does that fit with the rationale of Marbury, which confines the power of judicial review to decisions made by those who wrote and ratified the Constitution? Do not go too far is not a rule of law. It's not a rule at all. McCulloch founded the doctrine of tax immunity and then derivatively the anti-commandeering doctrine on a norm of separated powers. The original doctrine said that a tax was valid or not, depending on its object. That's a rule. The modern doctrine says that a tax is valid or not if the taxing authority imposes the same tax on its own property and workers. That too is a rule. When there can't be a rule, we have the first part of McCulloch-- as I phrased it, Chief Justice Marshall's second doctrine of judicial review. Outside the domain of the original rules, people are free to make their own decisions through elected legislatures. Now perhaps there's a way to convert national federation into a rule. By saying it to avoid the anti-commandeering doctrine, Congress always must offer a marginal payment for a marginal performance, and never may threaten to yank funds that have been the basis for some earlier consent by the states. But that's not what Chief Justice Roberts said. He did hint at the possibility, but it's not the basis of a holding. And that rule too would be hard to justify by anything along McCulloch's fashion. I'll come back to a potential reformulation of the anti-commandeering doctrine and its exception for side payments. Before that, however, I want to bring in the final doctrine-- sovereign immunity. The origin of sovereign immunity often is imputed to the 11th Amendment, which reads, "The judicial power of the United States shall not be construed to extend any suit in in law or equity, commenced or prosecuted against any one of the United States, by citizens of another state, or by citizens or subject of any foreign state." Close quote. This amendment, which responded to a decision that had allowed a private citizen to sue a state under the diversity jurisdiction, does not create a general rule of state immunity. It knocks out suits by citizens of other states, but does not address suits by citizens of the same state, suits that often could implement federal law. And ever since Hans against Louisiana announced a general doctrine of sovereign immunity in 1890, commentators had been saying that it's anti-textual. We have a real text, the 11th Amendment, which is more limited, and judges should not modify it to taste. If sovereign immunity were just judges thinking that they can do better than the 11th Amendment, then it would indeed be illegitimate. But from what I've said about tax immunities and the anti-commandeering principle, you should be able to see where this is going. Sovereign immunity is yet another illustration of the separation principle in McCulloch. Each set of governments is supreme within its sphere. Congress can no more authorize suits against the states than states can authorize suits against the National Treasury because governmental immunity doctrines are reciprocal. What states can't tax they can't make the subject of damages awards in litigation. And per McCulloch, the national government must give states the same leeway. If all this sounds very formal, well, it is. That was the intellectual style of the founding generations, and therefore how the interpretive community at the time understood the Constitution's text and structure. Osborn against the Bank of the United States made it clear just how formal this doctrine was, or at least was supposed to be. Ohio laid hold of some assets at the bank and the bank sued some state agent. Long before Ex parte Young, in 1908, announced what many people see as a dodge under which federal courts can order prospective relief against state officers by labeling them not the state and so outside the immunity doctrine, Osborn held that there's no problem suing state officers and forcing them to give the money back. Officers are not the state. The reciprocal immunity applies to units of government, but not anybody else. Just as it's possible to sue police officers who conduct unreasonable searches without any claim of sovereign immunity, so it's possible to sue state tax collectors who see money unlawfully. That's how Chief Justice Marshall saw things in 1824. Hans, in 1890, just reiterated the formal rule that you can't sue the state. Power was partitioned in 1787 and that's that. Well, that's that unless the Constitution gives Congress the power to regulate states directly in their role estates. Section 5 of the 14th Amendment gives Congress that power. And the Supreme Court accordingly held in 1976 that states sovereign immunity is not an obstacle. It later reached a similar conclusion about states as creditors in bankruptcy litigation. That understanding makes sense of almost all of the sovereign immunity cases, even those that have received the greatest academic criticism. The court held in Seminole Tribe against Florida that Congress can't abrogate state sovereign immunity, even when it has regulatory power under the commerce clause. How can the national government have the power to establish rules, but not the power to authorize litigation against states under those rules? The answer is McCulloch's. There can be power in either the state or federal governments to regulate the people, but not to regulate the other sovereign. That's a core part of McCulloch and of the anti-commandeering cases. When the Constitution allows regulation of a sovereign, as Section 5 does, then enforcement follows, for the same reason that McCulloch held that Congress, with the power to create the Bank of the United States, had the ancillary power to prevent its destruction. But two parts of sovereign immunity doctrine aren't understandable from this perspective, and I want to ask whether those exceptions don't show that sovereign immunity has exceeded the limits set by our two doctrines-- our two doctrines of judicial review, the one in Marbury and the one in McCulloch. One of these is an exception to sovereign immunity. Sovereign immunity doesn't apply to suits by the United States or one of its agencies, suits by states or suits by foreign nations. The justices say that immunity concerns private litigation only, but that's impossible to reconcile with McCulloch. If the national government has regulatory authority over states in their role as sovereigns, then the implication of McCulloch and the holding of the 1976 decision Fitzpatrick against Bitzer is that Congress can authorize anybody to sue. And if the national government lacks that authority, how can it enforce that non-authority by litigating in its own name? The second curious doctrine is that the national government sometimes can and sometimes can't insist that states entertain in their own courts suits based on federal law. The "can" holding, from 1947, is Testa against Katt. The "can't" holding, from 1999, is Alden against Maine. And I'm not interested in whether these cases are irreconcilable, as the majority and Alden concluded, or irreconcilable, as four justices contended in descent. What concerns me again is that this difference doesn't seem to have anything to do with whether the national government has regulatory authority over the states in their role as sovereigns, and therefore doesn't respond to the fundamental rationale of McCulloch. When oddities such as suits by the United States and the difference between Testa and Alden begin to accumulate, it's time to ask whether there isn't a problem with the doctrine. If the rationale of Marbury and McCulloch is what simultaneously legitimates and limits the related governmental immunity doctrines, shouldn't we now ask whether it's time for a correction that would bring the sovereign immunity and anti-commandeering doctrines into line with what's happened to the intergovernmental tax immunity doctrine? Remember what that was. One formal rule, no treading on the other sovereign's powers, was replaced by a different formal rule. Equal treatment, with limits set by vicarious representation. In the process, the political branches of both state and federal governments reclaimed power from the judiciary because both state and federal governments could now regulate in a neutral, nondiscriminatory way. Once the nondiscrimination principle becomes available, and we've seen how it can work, the limits of Marbury and McCulloch require a seating decision to elected officials. We'll consider how the equal treatment rule of tax immunities would apply to the anti-commandeering. You can't tell the states what to do would be replaced by, Congress may tell the states to do what the national government itself does. And current sovereign immunity doctrine would be replaced by, Congress may subject states to litigation in both state and federal courts when the national government is itself subject to enforcement litigation in both state and federal courts. Anomalies such as the difference between official and private litigation would vanish. The corollary to the anti-commandeering doctrine under which states can be paid, but not too much, would no longer have a role to play. And good riddance, I say, since, don't offer the states too much money is not a rule and it flunks the Marbury and McCulloch standard of judicial review. These revised doctrines wouldn't lead to much immediate change. Statutes in Prince and New York imposed on states duties that Congress was unwilling to impose on federal officials. They would flunk neutrality. And Congress has been unwilling to allow suit in state court against federal officials. That makes it hard to use an equal treatment principle to expose state officials to suit in federal court. If Congress fears that state courts would rule too often against federal interest, maybe it can understand why states are so reluctant to be sued in federal court. But whether or not Congress would take advantage of the opportunities created by restating all of the intergovernmental immunities as equal treatment doctrines, courts should be willing to do their part. A judicial claim, in the name of the unwritten constitution, depends on respecting the limits as well as the forms of Marbury and McCulloch. It's fundamentally illegitimate for judges to take judicial review as established and then use it to impose new restrictions on elected officials. Judicial review and the substance of the asserted constitutional doctrine are connected. Only those claims that satisfy Marbury and McCulloch are proper. I've tried to show you today how some unwritten doctrines meet the standards an originalist should apply, and how the need to justify judicial power simultaneously restricts the scope of those doctrines. Thank you very much. [APPLAUSE] Those of you who were not put to sleep by that talk may have some questions. So I'll be happy to entertain any questions. [LAUGHTER] DEAN MINOW: I'd be happy to start. That was just magnificent. So thank you so very much. I have a question that really has two parts. The conception of each sphere of government, entirely powerful within its own powers, is so compelling, but it seems remote from us. And ours is a much more pragmatic age, much more messy. So my first question is, do you think that that still is the conception that our Constitution stands for? And if so, does that mean we have to reverse a lot of decisions? But the related part is, how does relate to the supremacy clause? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Well, I hate to refer to "our Constitution" because our Constitution is strung out in time from 1787 to much more recent times. It's evident that the 14th Amendment is the product of a very different political and linguistic culture than the original ten amendments and the original Constitution. The point I was making, the basic point about the nature of judicial review, is that the rationale of Marbury demands that the court be able to understand the text as it would have been understood by the living interpretive community at the time of the text. And so we've got these differen. Times, and one of the central points I was making is that somebody who was there at the time and lived in that political culture can make a claim with much more assurance than somebody who wasn't there. Claims that the founding generation missed, misunderstood, or did not find constitutional rights that we've been able to see more recently, are almost always claims that are being invented by us rather than properly imputed to them. Right? That's the central part. And of course, as for the supremacy clause, it played a very important part in Chief Justice Marshall's rationale in Marbury. Without the supremacy clause, you don't have the hierarchy part of this justification. Then one might say, we've all just got a bunch of rules and they're on an equal plain and we'll go forward. You would have a very hard time justifying any judicial review without a supremacy clause. Yes? GARY LAWSON: Gary Lawson, Boston University. It occurs to me that an appropriate subtitle for this talk might be something like, the rule of law has a law of rules. [LAUGHTER] JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: That's been done. GARY LAWSON: Thank you. The question is whether that is in fact a constitutionally grounded norm and that the hypothetical would be this. Suppose we had a real live [? non-acromanian ?] constitutional amendment. Section 1, when Congress imposes-- JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: We've had 27 of them, I think. GARY LAWSON: When Congress imposes spending conditions on states, it cannot go too far. Section 2, federal courts shall have jurisdiction to entertain claims under Section 1. If one of those cases under that amendment came before you, would you think it would be an appropriate role under Marbury and McCulloch politely to decline the invitation on the ground that that amendment in Section 1 does not appropriately state a rule? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: I don't think we need an [? acromanian ?] amendment to do that. We've got one just like that. It's called the 4th Amendment. Right? The right of the people to be secure against in their persons' houses, papers, and effects against unreasonable searches and seizures and so on. It's got that word unreasonable in it. I don't doubt that it is within the power of constitution writers to confer on the government, and the government includes judicial officials the power to do that kind of thing. I get very skeptical if, for example, Congress were to pass a law saying it is reasonable, in our view, to use GPS locators to figure out where cars are, provided you do not commit a trespass in the course of installing the GPS locator. Right? I think it would be an inappropriate use of judicial power for the judges then to say, no dear Congress, you don't understand what reasonable is. We've got a different view of reasonable from the one you have. A word like reasonable is an authorization to adapt to changing times, but there's absolutely no reason why the judiciary could claim to have the only or dispositive word about what that word means. When it's a word appealing to changing times, we have people who make rules for changing times. Larry? LARRY LESSIG: So this is a very powerful conception of how background norms in this particular one that you've pointed to are critical to interpreting the text. And I guess the puzzle I have is how do we know or what's the standard for deciding that the background norm should be changed or recognized as change? For example, I know that the 18th Amendment is change because there's a 21st Amendment that explicitly changes it and has to go through a very elaborate process where states, 3/4 of the states, have to ratify that change. But how do I know that the judges are allowed to recognize a change in that background conception, the conceptual change that you've adopted by saying, for example, the explicit separation shall not be neutrality? And if I'm allowed to recognize it in some cases, what's the general rule for knowing in what other cases I'm allowed to recognize that background change? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: It's a very serious question. And my temptation is to answer it by saying you can't change the background assumption. You may be able to change our understanding of what works. For many of you, this may have seemed like this talk would never end, but it's unbelievably short compared to how long you would want to explain something like this. I do not think that what happened to the intergovernmental tax immunity doctrine was just a new generation having a different conception. I think that what happened to it was that the belief that powers could be hermetically separated-- the belief that everybody had at the time-- a belief that powers could be hermetically separated was found to be false. And then what is the closest approximation? And that, I think, turns out to be a neutrality rule. I believe somebody in this room, somebody who asked this question, has suggested that we have a concept of fidelity as translation when that kind of thing happens. And what I want to do, given who asked that question, is say that that does not mean that when the thing that is changed does not necessarily affect the original doctrine, that you can change the doctrine. I don't know whether everybody over there realized that Larry Lessig asked that question. He's written about fidelity as translation. And one of his articles suggested that you try to figure out how much authority the original framing generation wanted the commerce clause to convey and then see how that maps onto the modern world. Somebody like me is more likely to say, well, wait a minute. I can actually see a rule. What they enacted was a rule. They didn't enact their expectations. What they enacted was a rule. Congress has power over interstate commerce. And then the worlds changed so that there's much more interstate commerce than there used to be. It used to be rare for commerce to cross state borders. Now it's very common. Right? You pull out your iPhone and you realize it was just delivered from China. Right? By air. Not only is interstate and international commerce very common, but telecommunications are going up to geostationary satellites and coming back down. There's very little that stays within the states. My response to that is that we should not be trying to figure out what a commerce clause would look like to keep the federal government in the same relative role vis-a-vis the states. But how does something that's actually there in the text map onto a world that is fundamentally changed? But doing this inside of 60 minutes or inside the answer to the question is hopeless. Charles Fried? I hope some students will ask some questions eventually. [LAUGHTER] CHARLES FRIED: Frank, I'm drawn to your notion of the interpretive community at the time of the enactment. Let's take the 14th Amendment and the concept of equality. At the time of its enactment, I would suppose the interpretive community did not imagine that inequality included equality between men and women nor that it had the effect of depriving the federal government of making unequal rules to assist the former slaves. That probably wasn't what the interpretive community than thought. But they used the word equality. Isn't the method which you deplore, I think-- seems to me you're deploring it-- a method which says, well there was this notion of equality. They did invoke that. And that notion has a trajectory that is and outruns their particular limited vision of what the notion of equality was. Which are we bound to, the trajectory of the concept they invoked or the limitations on that concept under which they labored? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Well, as you should be clear from my answer to Larry, I don't think the meaning of a doctrine or of any text lies in people's expectations about the consequences that text will have. It lies in the rules it's laid down. And if you really want to think about what that means, suppose somebody passes a dollar a pack tax on cigarettes, and everybody in the legislature says, we're doing this because we think this will cut cigarette consumption by 50%. And it turns out and everybody believed that. It turns out it cut cigarette consumption by 10%, not by 50%. Could the tax people now collect a tax? Without the need for more legislation, could the tax people collect a tax of $5 because that would cut cigarette consumption by 50%? I think the answer would be no, right? The expectations about what would happen would not play a role in figuring out the meaning of the $1. I can get that meaning without thinking about expectations. That Charles gave that the 14th Amendment as an example, and I have to say that my view of the 14th Amendment is probably viewed as heretical. And I can tell that my view of the 14th Amendment is heretical because in a recent case, I wrote an opinion for the Seventh Circuit that tried to prod the Supreme Court to think about a different way of conceiving what the 14th Amendment does. It went to the Supreme Court. It was McDonald against Chicago. And my view got one vote, that of Clarence Thomas, and everybody else disagreed. But I learned this part of the Constitution at the feet of David Currie. And David thought that what the 14th Amendment principally did was that it principally contained the privileges or immunities clause. That was the real source of substance in it. It had a due process clause which, believe it or not, dealt with process and not with substance. And then it had an equal protection clause whose goal was to say that if the states protected white people from murder, it had to protect black people from murder, but didn't require the states to protect anybody from anything because the basic problem in construing an equal protection clause is always equal with respect to what. And if the original interpretive community understood that as equal with respect to protection against crime, then basically the only Supreme Court case that's ever been decided correctly under the Equal Protection Clause is McCleskey against Kemp. As I say, this is a heretical view. When the case came before the Supreme Court in McDonald, Justice Thomas was the only one who was willing to rethink and say the core of this is the privileges or immunities clause in the slaughterhouse cases were wrongly decided. The others were divided four to four between those who just don't like guns much and those who were all together uncertain about what was going to happen if the slaughterhouse cases were overruled and therefore preferred, dare I say it, to stick with Justice Brennan's we'll make it up as we all go along approach to incorporation of the 14th Amendment. So I'm sorry I haven't answered your question, but my-- [LAUGHTER] --my take on this may be sufficiently idiosyncratic that it's hard to give an answer. John Manning? Still no students? We got to do something about this. JOHN MANNING: I used to be a student. [LAUGHTER] JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Yeah, so did I. And that's why I hated the original package doctrine. JOHN MANNING: So I have a question about the interpretive community. So it's clear, as you've said, that if somebody kills another person in self-defense, even an unqualified murder statute is subject to the defense of self-defense because it's anticipated and established in advance by the interpretive community of lawyers that unqualified murder statutes are subject to that defense. Similarly, an unqualified statute of limitations is subject to the doctorate of equitable tolling, because when Congress passes those statutes, it passes them against an understanding of the relevant interpretive community lawyers, that that is an established, pre-existing defense to the statute of limitations. You say that there's a norm of separation that comes out of McCulloch. My question is how could that norm be a pre-existing norm against which the Constitution was adopted when the Constitution adopted a system of federalism that was novel and could not have had any antecedent expectations, A and B. If that's the case, isn't it true that what you're enforcing here are the expectations rather than the background conventions? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Oh, that's a deadly challenge. [LAUGHTER] I certainly hope I'm not enforcing anybody's expectations. To be accused of expectationism-- [LAUGHTER] --is very serious. But I don't think that it's true that in 1787 no one had experience with divided power. It's not simply the case that the United States had had Articles of Confederation, which provided powers and were imperfect because they didn't vest enough in the national government. Everybody was aware of the fact that powers were divided among the states. We grew out of a past in which powers were divided between the government and England and the residual powers in the colonies, which were operating under contracts. This was a perfectly normal way for people at the time to think. I don't think it was so unusual. Yes? MAN: Judge Easterbrook, [INAUDIBLE]. I'm a 2013 graduate. Think you for your-- JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: I'm still waiting for a law student then! [LAUGHTER] We're getting closer. MAN: As I understood your point about sovereign immunity, it rested on the importance of the liquidation of meaning by the interpretive community from which the text emerge-- that there was this general principle that we could infer about the quality of sovereigns in their own spheres, and from this we can drive sovereign immunity, if I understood your argument correctly. But I think that, with sovereign immunity in particular, there's another component to this which is the very specific text that you acknowledged in your lecture, which would seem to be itself a strong signal about the expectations and understandings of that particular interpretive community and how they understood sovereign immunity at the time. And in addition, there is more recent scholarship-- [? Professor Clark ?] on how sovereign immunity was in fact understood around the time of the 11th Amendment. So I wonder whether your general points about liquidation of meaning and the importance of McCulloch really does come up against a specific text in the case of the 11th Amendment. JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Well, if I thought that the 11th Amendment was trying to occupy the field of intergovernmental immunities, I would agree with that, but I don't. Not only because it didn't say this is the rule of sovereign immunity-- it was responding to a particular Supreme Court case-- but it didn't deal with the rest of the immunities. One of the points I was trying to make is that the immunity doctrines that I was looking at, intergovernmental tax immunity, anti-commandeering, sovereign immunity, are all of a piece. They're not separate things. They all flow in the same way from what was happening in McCulloch. And one might as well say the 11th Amendment got rid of the intergovernmental tax immunity doctrine because it didn't mention it. It was just what it was. It didn't try to occupy that field. At least that's how I see it. For what it's worth, by the way, I actually think of the 11th Amendment as an immunity. Caleb Nelson, who is a very careful and thoughtful and originalist scholar, thinks that the 11th Amendment, despite what it says, isn't about jurisdiction at all, but is about personal jurisdiction over states. One of the things I said in my talk is that judges aren't very good historians, and maybe I'm just demonstrating that. Maybe what I should have said is I'm just going with whatever Professor Nelson says, but that wasn't the way McCulloch had worked it out, and I've decided to go with the Chief Justice. CHRIS: Hi, my name is Chris [? Mirasol ?]. I'm a 1.0. JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Hooray! [APPLAUSE] CHRIS: So you just mentioned that there's a historical inquiry that has to happen if you're looking into the interpretive community around particular rules. On a case-by-case basis, how practical is it for judges to inquire into how people at that time would have interpreted it? How would they go about doing that? Or is it something that's on a larger basis that would happen once at a higher court? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: On a day-to-day basis, judges can't do it. Take, for example, the Supreme Court of the United States. They have cut their docket in half over the last 20 years, but they hear about 80 cases on the merits a year. That means that every justice on the Supreme Court is reading briefs on each side, plus a bunch of amicus briefs, in 80 cases, 200 working days a year. If you really, really work hard, and if each case got only one issue in it, and if you don't have to read cert petitions and decide what to grant and you can do nothing but spending all your time, you can spend two and a half days on a case. And that's not nearly enough to do this kind of research. It's utterly out of the question. So judges can't do their own historical research, and, of course, judges aren't trained as historians, nor are they trained as statisticians or as economists or as sociologists. Right? They have to rely to a great extent on the work done by professionals. And that has to mean that the number of these cases where important change can be made as few, and it also has to mean, I think, that judges have to be very conscious of their own limitations. Right? A professional scholar would spend several years trying to figure out what's behind this sovereign immunity doctrine. The judges have got to figure that out in two and a half days and move. CHRIS: Thank you. BROOKE: Hi. My name's Brooke and I'm also a 1.0. I just wanted to ask you-- the court system has sometimes been called counter-majoritarian or even undemocratic. And I was wondering if you think that a valid use in judicial review is for the courts to protect minorities from what could sometimes be the misguided or abusive power or will of the majority. JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: I think the function of judicial review is to carry out the decisions made and encoded in the Constitution. And there are a lot of people who might wish they had protections that never made it into the Constitution, but anything else is invention and it exceeds the judges' powers. There is a body that should be doing that. We call it Congress. JOSIAH: My name is Josiah, and I'm a 1.0. Sir, thank you for coming and speaking with us tonight. JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Delighted to be here. JOSIAH: I appreciate your emphasis on the original interpretive community as the baseline for approaching constitutional doctrines. And I wanted to ask you-- there are obviously many, including many at this school, who prefer to not perhaps ignore but discount the original interpretive community on grounds that we have progressed beyond that. How do you go about framing the debate over constitutional interpretation so as to best engage with people of the progressive philosophy? [LAUGHTER] JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: I would suggest that people of a progressive philosophy focus on articles one and two. The role of the judiciary in the Constitution is a very constrained one. And it is, as I remarked in explaining what tenure is for, the function of tenure is to make judges insensitive- the design function of tenure is to make judges insensitive to the needs of the present in order to be better at carrying out the decisions taken in the past. The institutions that are supposed to be sensitive to the needs of the present are Congress and the President. And on my view of judicial review, judges should not get in their way on the basis of made-up constitutional rights. JOSIAH: Thank you. MATT: Hi. My name is Matt. I'm a 3.0. I was just wondering, how do you deal with-- when using an originalist standpoint, how do you deal with the fact that the cases that you think got it wrong can be much closer to the original time, such as the Slaughter-House case that you mentioned? If you were dealing with an original conception, shouldn't they have known much better what their conception was? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Well, perhaps we should ask that question of Professor Lawson, who asked the first question or the second one, since Professor Lawson has written an article saying that stare decisis is itself unconstitutional, For the very reasons that Marbury gave this hierarchy of authority, what the Supreme Court has said about the Constitution is not itself part of the Constitution. So I don't think stare decisis has pride of place. As for the Slaughter-House cases, if you look at what happened, by the time the Slaughter-House cases reached the Supreme Court, the Hayes-Tilden election had substantially changed the American political landscape. Slaughter-House was divided five to four. Unlike the cases I've been talking about, which were nine to nothing, nine to nothing, nine to nothing, nine to nothing, were I think reasonably reliable indicators of what an earlier time was. The Slaughter-House cases were five to four and decided by votes of people who were, let us say, not really part of the coalition that gave us the 14th Amendment. ANNA LEIGH: Hi. Anna Leigh Curtis. I'm a 2.0. So you've said that judges' role is to enforce the Constitution as it would have been understood by people who were around in the interpretive community and nothing more. So how should-- JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Well, when you say nothing more, most of what judges do has nothing to do with that conception of judicial review. Almost all of what I do is enforcing statutes and dealing with common law. It's just a tiny, tiny, tiny slice of what judges do that I was talking about. ANNA LEIGH: Yeah, right. So suppose-- [LAUGHTER] Sorry. So suppose you have a constitutional question before you and what people would have understood that to mean at the time is absolutely clear, but you know the meaning at the time itself wasn't created democratically. So women, black people, other minorities weren't involved in the actual production of the meaning of those words. Is that a problem for originalism because it undercuts the democratic nature of-- JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: No. We always have to decide, at any time, whether we wish to be bound by these earlier documents. This is a revolutionary nation. We began in the Declaration of Independence with a declaration that if the government is tyrannical and not responsive to the people, it is both the privilege and the duty of the people to overthrow it. We, the living, have the power to overthrow old doctrines, but we have to do it either through the amending process or through revolution. Right? It's a revolutionary country we can act. But the idea that people who have tenure and can't be got rid of can decide to stage their own revolution is, I think, not satisfactory. It wasn't what the Declaration of Independence was about. STUDENT: My name is [INAUDIBLE]. I'm a 1.0 here. First, let me say thank you for coming. It's a great honor to hear from the man who's written so many of the opinions in our casebooks. JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: You've read them and survived. A [? shock. ?] STUDENT: Well, ask me again once finals get here. [LAUGHTER] So if I understand you correctly, it seemed like you had a bit of skepticism for judges who seem to take their own values to invent new doctrines and those sorts of things. You were oftentimes referred to as a leading figure in law and economics. So I wonder when you apply economic theory to cases, how do you make sure that's actually an objective standard and not just judges imposing a value through that? JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: That's a very serious question. The question is, how do judges try to escape the effects of their own beliefs? Justice Holmes said that every judge has his list of can't-helps, things he can't help doing. But a judge, if he's any good at his job, has to be aware of them and try to figure out a way around them. You raised the question of economics. I did economic analysis of law when I was a full-time professor of law. I still do economic analysis of law on the side. I write articles and antitrust and securities, written a book about the economic structure of corporate law. You have to be aware. The first question that you need to ask yourself as a judge is, what is it I'm supposed to do? When is it legitimate for me to consider that aspect of my thinking? So I pick up an antitrust case, and the Supreme Court has been saying now for quite some time that antitrust is effectively a branch of the common law and the judges are supposed to maximize the protection of consumers. And I think I know, economically, ways to do that. I feel no hesitation in writing antitrust cases in those terms. But here's a different one. The state of Wisconsin passed a law that effectively reverted to a very old rule of corporate law under which there couldn't be a merger unless all the stockholders approved, reverted to a unanimity rule. The first article I ever published in the Harvard Law Review dealt with how the target company's management should respond to a tenure offer. And Dan Fischel and I said in that article, after an economic analysis, basically roll over and play dead. Right? Allow the tenure offer to go forward and allow the shareholders to get the benefit. Wisconsin passes a statute which completely negates tender offers. And the Seventh Circuit was asked to hold that statute unconstitutional, essentially because it was injuring the non-Wisconsin shareholders of the Wisconsin Corporation. So I ended up writing that opinion. The first thing you have to do is decide what is your role. Is there a constitutional role for the judge to implement articles from the 1981 Harvard Law Review? We answered no, although I see John Manning shaking his head yes. [LAUGHTER] We answered no. I wrote an opinion saying that was a valid statute. It may be stupid, but of course, most statutes are stupid, so-- [LAUGHTER] How could you tell this apart? And Marty Lipton then sent a letter to all of his clients saying, well, if even Judge Easterbrook is going to uphold these statutes, you can tell the jig is up. All right? But that's the sequence of things you need to do. You need to ask, what is my role as a judge? Do I have a warrant to write my ideas about good policy into law? And in antitrust law, I think the answer is yes. And in corporate law, which is the domain of the states, I think the answer is no. And you try to behave accordingly. MAX: Good evening, Judge Easterbrook. My name is Max [INAUDIBLE]. I'm a 2.0. Thank you for coming. You've come at a great time. I recently decided to write a paper for Professor Manning critiquing one of your opinions. [LAUGHTER] JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: That sounds like an impossible task. [LAUGHTER] MAX: It's the [? USB ?] Marshall opinion, the one where you analyze whether LSD on blotter paper constituted a mixture under the statute. For what it's worth, I think you reached the right decision. [LAUGHTER] JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: And the Supreme Court thought I reached the right decision. [LAUGHTER] MAX: My contention is that you could have been a little more textualist. [LAUGHTER] JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: Can I answer from behind this? [LAUGHTER] MAX: In particular, applying the tenants of interpretation, I think the term "mixture of substance" should have been interpreted as a chemistry term of art. And I was wondering if you could talk about how you approach statutory interpretation, whether you have a set method, whether you run through all the cannons, and how you balance when cannons point different ways. JUDGE FRANK EASTERBROOK: OK. I don't know how many in this room know Marshall. Those of you who do would probably be best off not. [LAUGHTER] There's a statute which says that the sentence you get for distributing drugs, and this includes LSD and heroin and cocaine and a bunch of other things, methamphetamine, depends on the total weight of the quote mixture or substance containing that drug. Normally, for drugs like cocaine, powder cocaine-- powder cocaine is often cut, and so it's not 100%. Sometimes it's quite diluted. But for LSD, the dilution rate is incredible. Imagine LSD-- if you think of a drop of LSD, the amount of LSD in it is just trivial compared to the drop. You put the drop in a sugar cube. The water all evaporates, and then you take the sugar cube and you get the LSD-- well, "you" figuratively. [LAUGHTER] The weight of the sugar cube compared to the weight of the LSD is something like 20,000 to one. So effectively people are being punished for the weight of the sugar or the weight of the blotter paper, which is another way of distributing it. And the question was whether the statute authorizes the punishment to be based on the weight of that substance. Stephen Breyer, when he was on the First Circuit, had a case in which cocaine was cooked into the frame of an attache case. So the cocaine was mixed with the plastic, and the question was whether the weight of the attache case was the weight for which somebody was going to be sentenced. I wrote an opinion for the Seventh Circuit saying that mixture of substances is construed in a lay fashion because I didn't think Congress knew very much about chemistry. And that led to the conclusion that it counted, and there was a very vigorous dissent. The Supreme Court affirmed the Seventh Circuit. So it counts. And of course, what's then happened is what sensibly ought to have happened. Many of these statutes have been amended, although, I think not the one about LSD, curiously. The question whether if you're trying to figure out how to understand a phrase like "mixture of substance" you turn to the interpretive community of chemists, is very difficult. Normally if you're thinking about the meaning of something, you think about the interpretive community of the people who will be talking about that subject. So editorial pages, perhaps. That's where Crosskey and Fairman were looking to try to figure out the meaning of the Commerce Clause. Chemists would be a very unusual place to turn, unless there was some reason to believe that the word was being used technically. One of my favorite cases is a case called Nix against Hedden. Some of you may have read it. Congress imposes a tax on fruit, a duty on fruit. And a tomato arrives at the border, and the importer says, this is a vegetable. And the government says, no this is a fruit. You better pay the duty. And the important question was, OK, if you look around you and you ask a botanist what a tomato is, the botanist will say, it's a fruit because it's got internal seeds. And any great school student will say it's a vegetable because it tastes sour and my parents serve it to me like vegetables. [LAUGHTER] The technical question in the case was whether Congress was more like a botanist or more like a grade school student. [LAUGHTER] And the Supreme Court answered, more like a grade school student. [LAUGHTER] And I have that same sense in Marshall, and I'm willing to defend it. [LAUGHTER] [APPLAUSE] DEAN MINOW: Judge Easterbrook invoked Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr., who once said "Every idea is an incitement. Eloquence may set fire to reason." I want to thank Justice Scalia for your incitement, your eloquence, your reason and inspiring this outstanding lecture series. And I want to thank Judge Easterbrook for your incitement, your reason, your eloquence. And we're going to be arguing for a long, long time. Thank you all for being here. [APPLAUSE]
Info
Channel: Harvard Law School
Views: 89,720
Rating: 4.6151204 out of 5
Keywords: Frank Easterbrook, Antonin Scalia, Harvard Law School, Martha Minow
Id: yuAyxQr2LYE
Channel Id: undefined
Length: 92min 25sec (5545 seconds)
Published: Thu Nov 20 2014
Related Videos
Note
Please note that this website is currently a work in progress! Lots of interesting data and statistics to come.