Today our focus is on Tachyons, a hypothetical
particle that travels faster than light and has an imaginary mass, and even more so on
time travel, which we need to talk about before we get to some of the other subjects like
wormholes. Last time we talked about the basics of Special
Relativity when it came to making time slow down and we cleared up some confusion people
often have with that subject before talking about Quantum Entanglement. Today we’ll be expanding on those notions
a bit so if you haven’t already watched the first episode you should do that now unless
you have a pretty solid grasp of Special Relativity already. Which is to say if you’ve seen these two
equations before and used it several times you’re good, otherwise not. Now these equations didn’t show up last
time but ought to look fairly familiar. Last time we talked about distance and time
contracting, today we are more interested in mass. So we’ve three new quick concepts to look
at. Rest mass, the Lorentz Factor, symbolized
by the lowercase Greek Gamma, and the Capital Greek Beta. That last one is the easiest, when we are
dealing with truly relativistic velocities we always talk in terms of the speed of light. Something is going .9 c, or .5 c, and we just
use Beta for that, if Beta equals .5 then you are going at half the speed of light. Saves time and makes for a smaller equation. The Lorentz Factor, Gamma is much the same
thing, if you calculate gamma for any given speed you can just multiply or divide it by
your proper length or time to find out how much time is dilated or length is contracted. You can also multiply it by rest mass to figure
out what the relativistic mass is. Now rest mass is a simple concept but has
some tricky aspects. It is literally how much mass something has
when measured when it isn’t moving, when it is at rest. But we usually don’t use non-rest mass,
relativistic mass, in favor of just keeping that invariant and thinking in terms of the
objects total energy. So we use energy, momentum, and rest mass
energy together a lot. This makes gamma way more convenient but also
means we often like to talk in terms of gamma, not Beta, since its effects are more intuitively
obvious. I mentioned last time that an object moving
at 87% of light speed, or Beta = .87, would appear to be scrunched up in the direction
of motion by half and have its clock running at half speed, and that one doing 97% would
be condensed down to a quarter and have time running at a quarter speed. That’s the case for gamma equal 2 and for
respectively, and that’s easier to think with. Here on this table I have selected gammas
by their beta value. And as gamma rises time slows down more and
more and the energy you need to get to that speed rises sharply. As you can see you never quite reach Beta
= 1, or light speed, until gamma is infinite, meaning anything with rest mass needs infinite
energy to get to light speed. And you’d need more than infinity, something
of a nonsensical concept, to accelerate anything with rest mass over light speed. Of course if anything started off with that
speed to begin with, like our tachyons, they wouldn’t need infinite energy to get there,
same as photons don’t need infinite energy to be at the speed of light since they have
no rest mass. This is where imaginary mass comes into play. If you pump in a value for Beta of more than
1, say 1.41, then Beta Squared equals 2 and 1-2=-1. Now we have a problem again because there’s
no real solutions to the square root of a negative number. That’s why Rene Descartes, best known for
“I think therefore I am”, created what we call an imaginary number, i, which when
multiplied by itself equals -1. Hopefully you’re already familiar with that
because I don’t want to spend time discussing it, but odds are good you don’t know that
the reciprocal of i is –i, so when we get 1 over i here we can just replace it with
–i, giving us a negative imaginary gamma and a negative imaginary mass. We don’t really care about that negative
and don’t usually mention it to avoid confusing with negative mass, which we’ll be talking
about a lot when we get to the Alcubierre Warp Drive and stable Wormholes, so we usually
just say imaginary mass. Now imaginary numbers bug people, especially
in terms of physics which unlike math is only supposed to deal with reality, but imaginary
numbers come up a lot in physics, and even trigonometry features them though we usually
hide it. And imaginary mass isn’t limited to tachyons,
this hypothetical particle now in disfavor, we use it for tachyonic fields for the Higgs
Boson too. We also use imaginary time in Cosmology. Conceptually the easiest way to explain the
tachyon running back in time is just to think how as time slows down as you approach the
speed of light, freezing at the speed of light, that it just starts running backwards above
the speed of light. Now Tachyons are a whole class of particles,
anything which might move faster than light. We don’t assume it to be a single particle
like an electron. In this context we also have the luxon, any
massless particle like the photon or gluon that travels at the speed of light and experiences
no internal time, and the Bradyon or Tardyon. Tachyon comes from the Greek word for rapid,
and Tardy is Latin for slow, whereas Brady is Greek for slow so Bradyon is probably more
consistent but neither gets used much. But a Bradyon, or Tardyon, would be any normal
matter with a rest mass. The application of the Tachyon is obvious. If you can generate them then you can send
them back to a given place and time to be received. Time travel telephone or radio, and presumably
something you could use to send people back in time too, or homicidal androids. The tachyon was first proposed in the early
sixties, though it was known as a metaparticle at the time and soon renamed. It made a couple appearances in science fiction
novels in the seventies but its first use I know of in TV or film was in Doctor Who,
during the episode the Leisure Hive whose last installment amusingly was on the day
I was born. That combined with the obvious time travel
application of a particle that moves back in time is why the intro for this series has
the doctor who theme. It’s going to come up a lot in the series
because there are not many situations where you can travel faster than light without traveling
back in time. I wanted to discuss these issue of Temporal
Paradoxes back in episode 1 but I didn’t want to run overly long and Time Travel, pardon
the pun, is a time consuming subject. Time travel and its paradoxes tend to give
people headaches, probably because its use in fiction necessitates it not quite making
sense, but today we’ll be trying to explain how it works minus the headache. That pretty much ends our interest in the
Tachyons though, they are simply a vehicle to time travel and their hypothetical status
means we have no proof they exist, they might not exist, and we have no idea how we’d
ever detect them if they did. So let’s move on to time travel. Fortunately it’s also a topic you are probably
already acquainted with. The two classic examples, in terms of paradox,
are known as the Grandfather Paradox and the Casual Loop. There are some other ones, but they usually
represent the same thing under a different name or minor thematic rather than functional
variation. The Grandfather Paradox is when you go back
in time and keep your grandparents from every meeting, this causing you to never be born,
thus preventing you from ever traveling back in time to prevent that meeting, erasing the
problem. In terms of alternate timelines or Many Worlds
theory this can have different effects we’ll come back to in a bit. The Casual Loop is the other angle on the
paradox. Casual Loops, as the name implies, are where
effect precedes the cause, or has a sort of chicken and egg thing going on. An event causes another event which in turn
causes the original one. A loop of cause and effect, or a causal loop. The evil computer intelligence finds itself
losing a war with the human resistance and notes that the leader of the resistance seems
to be an abnormally larger factor in the loss and deduces that if he had never existed the
resistance would never have existed either or been far weaker. So he sends a murderous robot back in time
to prevent the birth of said resistance leader by killing his mom. The resistance leader sends his own guy back
in time to protect his mom who then ends up being his father and forewarns the mother
of a lot of the problems, so she ends up raising a kid who really is an abnormally skilled
resistance leader, leading the machine overlord to correctly deduce that removing him from
play before the game even got started would be a smart move. In the grandfather paradox you never travel
back in time to kill Hitler because having killed him you erase your motivation to travel
back in time and do it again. In the casual loop paradox, you get this chicken
and egg aspect, your time travel ends up causing your reason for time travel. Skynet decides he has to eliminate John Connor
in the past, not now, because he made the resistance so much more dangerous, but the
reason for that was because the attempted assassination resulted in him having the foreknowledge
and training to be dangerous. This is why casual loops are also called Retrocausality,
pulling yourself up by your own bootstraps, or Self-Fulfilling Prophecies. Now we need to talk about Quantum. In Quantum Physics there are numerous interpretations
of seeming Quantum Randomness. The two you’re most familiar with are Copenhagen
and Many Worlds. We don’t really have a way to test which
is true, if any, because they are all designed to match what evidence we do have. Copenhagen looks at Schrodinger’s Cat and
says the critter is simultaneously alive and dead until you look. I prefer to think of it as coin that’s spinning,
simultaneously heads and tails, until you grab it, since I like cats. Plus I think a spinning coin better represents
the concept of an undetermined state. In Many Worlds you don’t know the result
until you observe it but it assumes the event actually spawned two different realities,
one alive, one dead, or one heads, one tails. The result is already determined, you can’t
predict which universe you’re in but the contents of the box or the coin flip are already
resolved you just need to check them. Time Travel is mostly not a problem in Many
Worlds. If you jump back in time you just spawn a
new timeline. In fact there ought to be a version of reality
right now where by sheer quantum randomness various atoms in your front lawn have coalesced
into a blue police box some gentleman just stepped out of, complete with detailed but
fake memories of time travel. That’s the irritating thing about quantum,
since any given atom has a finite chance to change into another atom, there is a much
smaller chance of two of them doing it at about the same time and place, and a far smaller
but still finite chance of that happening in many atoms to produce some macroscopic
and weird thing out of nowhere like and individually wrapped candy bar or a person possessing an
entirely randomly created memory. So in many worlds there’s already a reality
in which someone has appeared genuinely thinking they’re a time traveler even though they
didn’t even exist till five seconds ago. This concept is merely an extension of the
notion of a Boltzmann Brain, in a truly random system any state that can exist will eventually
exist, and that would include a brain, complete with everything it needs to keep surviving,
like a body, assembling itself randomly, and that can also include a fake memory, leading
that entity and other people to assume they existed before, a concept we’ll look at
from a different angle when we discuss the Simulation Hypothesis. But real time travel is nominally viable in
Many Worlds anyway, since you wouldn’t even risk a paradox so long as you were jumping
to a time, ahead or behind, in a reality that was not your own. And it need differ by nothing more than that
a single random uranium atom in the core of the planet that did decay into thorium and
Helium five seconds ago in our reality did not do so in the one you want to jump ahead
in time into. Or a version of the past where an atom of
uranium still around now had previously decayed as Julies Caesar was born, and events are
otherwise effectively identical. It’s not your past or future you are messing
with so no paradox is created by your actions. You need not even necessarily be moving in
time anyway, as a parallel reality might simply have time running there a bit slower or faster
so you are simply stepping into a place that is otherwise identical but a bit further ahead
or behind your own time. In many worlds it’s kind of debatable if
going to those other worlds is really the same as time travel or not, but from a practical
standpoint it is. Of course you could still setup a casual loop
in this setup too, though it might be better to think of it as a wave. You get your hands on a time machine, or reality
jumping machine, and wait till the next news report of some big gold strike on relatively
cheap land or some other event less random than the lottery, like a new tech patent,
and jump a bit back in time into a reality where a copy of you exists waiting for such
data too, hand it off to him and he takes off, leaving you there to assimilate into
a near-identical circumstance but now very rich due to your knowledge. He arrives in the next carbon copy and cuts
the same deal with your other quantum clone and rinse and repeat until eventually some
difference exists that breaks the chain and the wave crashes to an end. This isn’t a casual loop in that chicken
and egg sense since you had a definite starting and stopping point. Now the Copenhagen Interpretation, that our
cat or coin is in two states at once until observed, doesn’t actually prohibit alternate
timelines or other realities, it simply has no need for them. There’s tons of different ways you can have
places besides our own Universe after all, and some of our other FTL concepts for instance
would involve popping into a parallel Universe, meaning one that has bits and pieces corresponding
to our own, that was smaller than our own or had a higher speed of light and just zipping
through there until you reached that point of congruity and popping back into our own
Universe. But again in Copenhagen there’s no need
for these alternate realities, and we often assume there is just a single timeline. After all an issue with Many Worlds, an incorrect
one but a common concern, is that these branching new realities are all new universes forming
from nothing and breaking energy conservation, or getting you something from nothing. Which considering our own universe is assumed
to have violated that in the first place shouldn’t be a big concern but normally in many worlds,
or in some variations of it, the assumption is these alternate universes already existed
and always have. Think of it as alternate pasts, not just alternate
futures. More than one state of affairs can lead to
an identical final result, a concept that relates to our next concept, and would still
apply even though it assumes there are no alternate timelines. In the context of Copenhagen Interpretation,
with no alternate timelines or realities, or at least where if they do exist they are
inaccessible, we have something called the Novikov Self-Consistency Principle. Igor Novikov, who came up with the Novikov
self-consistency principle of time travel, argued temporal paradoxes weren’t possible. He closes out paradoxes in time travel, which
are permitted in some solutions of the Einstein Field Equation for General Relativity, by
asserting any event that would give rise to a paradox or change the past in anyway must
have a probability of zero. This doesn’t ban time travel in and of itself
though. It simply is arguing that any time travel
has to result in no paradox or it would be infinitely improbable to occur. Novikov is arguing that regardless of whether
or not time travel is possible, you will not be able to do anything that causes a paradox. In a conceptual sense, don’t think of this
as some sort of Time guardian who pops out and stops you, but rather that the moment
you take a paradoxical route things would reset to a scenario where you hadn’t taken
it yet and keep doing it until you picked a path that didn’t cause that. Since in Copenhagen there is always a chance
one of the random quantum events will spiral itself up to the macroscopic level one will
eventually occur that results in a non-paradoxical action. There’s no deletion, our coin that can normally
be heads or tails will simply never land on heads if it doing so would cause a paradox. You would not remember these resets of course,
they will have never happened for the same reason that once you open Schrodinger’s
box or catch the coin, the observed reality erases the alternate possibility, and as we
discussed with Quantum Entanglement, that erasure is not constrained by the speed of
light nor does it even seem to care if it has to reach back in time to fix it. Again this isn’t implying anything is selecting
that solution that counters the possible paradox, there would be many that did, and many that
didn’t, and one would happen same as a drop of water falling from the sky will eventually
take a path leading to the ocean, whether it does so by falling right into the ocean,
or on your roof and following drainage ditches and waterways to the ocean, or even falling
on a desert and evaporating. The Self-Consistency Principle tends to bug
people a bit as confusing since it sort of seems like a tautology. Paradoxes are impossible because paradoxes
are impossible, but the difference is that it’s asserting the laws of physics can’t
be chucked out the window by time travel. There’s a comment on this that this principle
seems to permit any type of action can be done through time travel except killing yourself,
since you obviously can’t travel back in time if you’re dead. I’d say even that doesn’t work though,
and something will happen to resurrect you, like one of those freak quantum events I mentioned
earlier where a blue police box and guy with fake memories of time travel is spontaneously
spewed out by quantum randomness. Or someone discovers cloning and mind uploading,
something we’ll be talking about in the future. Again it’s not that something is stopping
specific actions, it’s just that all your possible state and actions will only be non-zero
probabilities when they won’t cause a paradox. Now Novikov’s views are hardly considered
canon, however it comes up a lot in time travel talk so I wanted to discuss it. Same reasoning as the Tachyon, although in
the tachyon’s case, while it has fallen a bit out of favor in science fiction it has
seen a recent in resurgence in all sorts of pseudoscience especially for methods of immortality,
and again we’ll be looking at that subject ourselves soon, though we will be mostly focusing
on plausible science. Next time in this series we’ll be looking
at the Alcubierre Warp Drive, taking our first dip into how general relativity allows us
to warp spacetime, and another type of exotic matter, particles and fields possessing negative
mass or energy. From there we will move on to wormholes, which
rely on many of those same general relativity concepts and negative mass as well. I haven’t decided on an exact order to the
next few videos since I want to redo the old Dyson Dilemma video without having to interrupt
our regular schedule, but subjects we’ll be looking at in the near future in no particular
order will be a return to the Habitable Planets Series for a look at Double Planets, a return
to Megastructures series for a quick look at Hoopworlds, neither of which are going
to require very long videos so will probably be sooner than later. We’ll also be taking a deep look at the
Simulation Hypothesis, the concept that we might all be living in a giant simulated Universe,
and some of the implications that would have in regard to the Fermi Paradox. As well as an introduction to the concept
of transhumanism and biological immortality and especially the latter’s implications
to the Fermi Paradox. If we get a chance we’ll look into the Carter
Doomsday Argument and its own implication for the Fermi Paradox, and as you might guess
this jump back into the Fermi Paradox is a major motivation for finally redoing the Dyson
Dilemma, and if I get a chance the Fermi Paradox Solutions video as well. So a busy next couple months, assuming I can
hold to the current weekly schedule. If you want alerts when new videos come out,
subscribe to the channel. And if you enjoyed this video make sure to
like it and share it around for others. In the meantime, try out some of these other
videos, and as always comments and questions are welcome below. Thanks for watching and we’ll see you next
time.