Hey Vsauce! Michael here. And here. Michael here! hey vsauce! what is here? ā¦. what is there? what is there? What REALLY exists? Do waves exist or are there just things that
are wavy? When does a piece of food Iāve eaten stop
being food and become me? Do chairs exist? Ontology is the philosophy of existence. And chairs are what philosophers call ORDINARY
OBJECTS. Ordinary objects are the plain old common
sense things we deal with every day: spoons, buckets, rocks, stuff like that. Their existence is as obvious as possible but the more we try to sus out where they
are, the more sus they become. First of all, sure, this could all be a dream. Maybe weāve all been hallucinating chairs
all these years. Or this could part of the simulated reality
pumped into our brains while our bodies are harvested for energy. But underneath that skepticism thereās a
deeper ONTOLOGICAL question that we need to answer first. Regardless of whether this spoon is made of
real atoms or simulated atoms, is it really possible to be āmade ofā something? Take a look at these two things. As we all know, two minus one is ā¦ TWO?! There ARE two things here: An origami crane AND a piece of paper. Iām kidding, of course, thereās really
just one: the crane and the piece of paper are the same. But watch this. Whereād the crane go? If the paper and the crane were truly identical,
they would share everything in common. But clearly they donāt: the paper can survive
being unfolded, the crane cannot. Also, I made the crane, but I didnāt make
the paper. And the paper was around before the crane. For two things that are the same, they sure
are different. This relationship is called CONSTITUTION:
paper constitutes the crane. Itās a one-to-one relationship, but thereās
another kind of ābeing made ofā going on here, too. This paper is made not of ONE other thing,
but of sextillions of things: fundamental subatomic particles: electrons and quarks,
or strings, or physical and virtual fields. This many-to-one relationship is called COMPOSITION. Philosophers call whatever it is that matter
is ultimately composed of SIMPLES: a simple is a thing that, unlike a piece of paper,
has no parts. No substructure. Not even a top or bottom. It could be the case that there are no simples,
that thereās just a never-ending chain of smaller and smaller substructure. Philosophers call such a reality a GUNKY universe. If structure never ends in the other direction
and everything turns out to be part of something bigger with no final complete composite, thatās
whatās known as a JUNKY universe. Point is: believing ordinary objects exist
and are made up of smaller things is quite common. Itās called ontological reductionism. Itās the position that wholes are NOTHING
MORE than their parts. But our cranes and our paper challenge that notion.
it seems like being MADE OF some things IS different than just BEING those things. Letāās agree on what it means to exist. Letās say that for something to exist is
simply for there to be more than zero of it. Pegasus exists if we mean āare there any
winged horses in works of fiction and mythology?ā And pegasus does not exist if we mean, āare
there any physical, flesh-and-blood winged horses that evolved on Earth through natural
selection.ā okay, so if we can agree on that, then of course chairs
exist! Thereās this one right here. I can see it and feel it and taste it. yea. Itās dry and .. a little bit salty. Dry and salty are what we call PROPERTIES. Properties tell us what things are LIKE. For example, this slice of cheese is FLOPPY. By noticing and sharing properties, we can
let each other know what to expect from things. And we all more or less agree on what things
there are. We give names to stuff and if they catch on,
we put them in dictionaries with the word ānounā next to them. But are all of these nouns an inventory of
the universe ā¦ or an inventory of things we MADE? Let me put it this way: do islands exist? Well, itās in the dictionary and a quick
look around confirms that there are more than zero islands, so yes. Islands exist. But what about incars? An incar is a car that is IN a garage. As a car leaves a garage, an incar diminishes
at the threshold until it collapses into nonexistence. Later, an extremely similar incar may emerge
at the same threshold when the car returns. Are there any cars in garages right now? If so, then incars exist. You might be thinking, āthatās not a thing. you just made that up. And itās silly: ābeing in a garageā
is just a property that a car can have. Stop trying to make incars a thing.ā Ok, first of all, I didnāt make it up, Eli
Hirsch did. And second of all, if you think incars arenāt
things, wait till you hear about islands. An incar might just be a relation between
a car and a garage but an island is just a relation between land and some water. Now, āislandā might be a more useful concept
than āincar,ā but does that make islands OBJECTIVELY more real than incars? And what about trogs? A trog is an object whose parts are a tree
and whatever dog is nearest. Hereās a picture of one. Do you see the trog? this is its tree part
and this is its dog part. You might be thinking, come on, how can THAT
be a thing? The tree and the dog arenāt even connected! well so what? These two pieces of fabric arenāt connected
and yet theyāre a thing called a bikini. Now sure, if we cut down this tree and burn
it for warmth, we wouldnāt feel the need to apologize to whatās left of the trog
for destroying its tree part. But maybe we should? What if some extraterrestrials showed up and
said they thought dogs and trees composed trogs ā would they be wrong? Could we convince the otherwise? Ontological realists believe that we could. That there really is a mind-independent answer
to the question, āwhat is there?ā People like Theodore Sider believe that the
universe has ājointsā and we can cut up reality up into objective, real things by finding
them. Ontological anti-realists disagree. Their position is that what we think there
is is just one way to cut up reality. Itās a good one for us and our needs, but
itās not objectively more true than any other. So whoās right? Hmmā¦ well if these blocks compose
a tower ā¦ what do they compose now? Just because we donāt have a name for .. this..
doesnāt necessary mean that I havenāt accidentally built something. Does it? When DO two or more things compose something
else? Peter Van Inwagen calls this the special composition
question. In MATERIAL BEINGS he considers possible answers:
maybe things compose something only when theyāre in contact. Thatās a good thought, but it doesnāt
explain how a BIKINI can be a thing. Or why two books are still just two books
when one is stacked on top of the other. you know, Maybe a certain degree of FIXATION is required. Or a āmeldingā ā¦ if a surgeon sewed
us together and the skin healed with no seam and we shared the same blood supply ā¦ you
know, even then it would seem wrong to say that weād become some new kind of animal. Thereād still just me and you. But like, stuck together. The philosophy of parts and wholes is called
mereology and Mereological Universalism is the belief that
thereās an answer to the special composition question and the answer is this: any assortment of stuff, no matter
how strange or scattered across time and space composes a thing. some pages compose these books but I don't just have two books here. Oh no, there's also a third thing let's call it a "took" because it's parts are Two Books. There is also something composed of my left ear,
the northern third of every brown trout in England, and the Eiffel tower. Just because it has no name and no oneās
ever talked about it before just shows a lack of intrest on our parts. To a universalist, eliminating some composites
but not others is just too arbitrary. We may as well accept them all. Eliminativism is any belief that accepts some
composites, but eliminates others. Peter Van Inwagen, for example, believes that
there are no ordinary objects, no chairs or shirts or shoes. Right here there are just some simples ā atoms or whatever
ā arragned show-wise. There isn;t something else here called a shoe. But he thinks that because people believe
they themselves exist, and he canāt see how something could believe it existed without
existing in the first place to even think that, there must be people. He goes further, though, to argue that ALL
living thigns exist. While admiting he doesnāt have any āknock-downā
agruments in their favor, he mentions that because simples that are part of a living
organism maintain the organism ā ā while shedding some members and gaining
others, all while remaining individuated from other organisms, unlike, say, waves of water
at the moment of collision, clearly, simples in the act of a life must compose something. That position is ORAGANICISM. Itās been called the belief that people
exist, but that none of them wear clothes. Mereological Nihilism is less generous. Itās the belief that there arenāt any
trogs or incars OR dogs or trees. Because nothing ever composes. The nihilist doesnāt believe that there
is NOTHING here. There are lots of simples, but thatās it. That might sound puzzling: how can a bunch
of fundamental particles, arranged into atoms and molecules that are arranged like this
NOT be a chair? Thatās JUST IS what a chair is! Good question. Letās call that deflationism: the belief
that this is all silly and that all of these positions are talking past each other: they
all agree on what reality contains: they all believe that there are simples here and that
those simples are arranged in a chair shape. Since thatās just what a chair IS, they
all believe in chairs. Those who say they donāt just being weird
and contrarian. Deflationism has many supporters. And it truly is the heart of our issue today. But to address it, we should first see why
it would be nice if all of these parts did not form a chair. Letās begin with over-determination: If
chairs really do exist, shouldnāt they be able to interact with us? The thing is, though, everything this alleged
chair can do can be described by referencing the behavior of simples here and any other simples
that come along. An account of the activities of every ATOM in this room, leaves nothing for the chair to explain. Composites are causally redundant. Believing in chairs is like believing that,
while yes, the burning gas from my stove completely describes why the water in a pot boils, thereās
ALSO a magical invisible substance called boil-o that comes out of my stove that does
the same thing as the flame at the same time and if there was no boil-o the flame would
warm the water just the same, but there is boil-o. Chairs are no more real than boil-o. Composites over-determine what happens in the world. They also lead to over-COUNTING. For more on that, letās say hello to this
videoās sponsor. Hi. Iām Michael Stevens. You may know me from such films as āLady
Gaga - Judas PARODY! Key Of Awesome #42ā and The Emoji Movie. But today, Iām here to talk to you about
the Curiosity Box. This season, subscribers will be receiving
many things, including a shirt celebrating the Sherman line, a kit to find out what bacteria
is growing on you, a puzzle that celebrates the average color of neptune and yes, uranus,
and the first ever at-home demonstration of impossible colors. And right now, if you subscribe with code BOGO, weāll
also send you our entire summer box completely free. just pay shipping How many THINGS will you be receiving for
one ridiculously low price? You might think 15: 8 things plus 7 things. But donāt forget that youāre ALSO
getting this entire collection and THIS entire collection. Thatās 17 things! ORder now. Thatās a good deal, but the ontology seemed
wrong. If I count some parts, I shouldnāt also
count the whole they compose. But if you believe in composite objects you
MUST do this, right? After all, the composite exists. So if this chair contains, say, 100 sextillion
atoms, then there are actually AT LEAST 100 sextillion and one things here: all of these
atoms and also a chair. That seems wrong.. but wait, thereās more. If I take a knife and scrape off a tiny part
of this chair ā¦ is it still a chair? I think most of us would say yes. It would still be a chair even if I removed
a tiny bit again. And again. A series of tiny innocuous removals is called
a SORITES SEQUENCE. The trouble they cause is that while it seems
we must accept that each individual step doesnāt annihilate the chair, clearly, ENOUGH minute
removals WILL eventually leave us with no chair. Nothing at all, in fact. But how can that be? How subtracting zero over and over again EVER
give a different result? Clearly, there must be a point at which a
tiny change DOES make a difference. Different people might give different answers
as to where that line is ā but, you know, we could just stipulate the boundaries: we
could define āchairā in some extreamly precise way. If we did that, if we defined the shape, function,
history, and use that makes something a chair so precisely that the even the smallest deviation
would make or break its status as a chair ā¦ how could we know if itād done it right? If we called up God and said, āhey dude,
watch this, see this chair? Okay, now weāre going to remove a single
atom from it. Ta da! Itās no longer a chair is it?ā Would God would be like, āpwha! Correct! you guys nailed it. That is exactly right. It was a chair before and now, in my infinite
wisdom, I can confirm that that single atom was what made the difference.ā Unless thereās some explanation for why
a boundary should be drawn in a precise way instead of some other way, our stipulations
are just arbitrary. Ordinary objects may be unredeemably vague. But being vague may actually be a feature of ordinary
objects. For example, how many people is a crowd? 10 people standing together in a huge empty
park might be more of a group, but 10 people standing further apart in a tiny waiting room
will feel way more CROWDED. The fact that our terms depend on context,
that theyāre PLASTIC, make it seem less and less like theyāre describing THINGS
and more and more like theyāre pragmatic. That rather than telling what there is, they
tell us to expect. Peter Unger has pointed out that thereās
at least one kind of thing that CAN survive a sorities sequence without paradox: stuff. If you innocuously remove pieces from something
that is just āsome stuffā you will still have some stuff after each step until you
reach a clear and unambiguous boundary: when the last piece is removed, there will no longer
be any stuff. This might show that there ARE composite objects:
stuff. As soon as we pretend that some stuff is a
THING, though, vagueness sets in. Suddenly weāre talking about a thing that
can lose parts but also canāt lose parts and unless contradictions can exist, words
like āchairā donāt really refer to any thing in the universe. Sorites seqeunces lead to other problems,
too. Like: the PROBLEM OF THE MANY. If removing a tiny number of atoms from this chair still
leaves me with a chair, how many chairs are here? I mean, thereās this one. And then thereās this one, which is really similar to the first but doesn't have these atoms on top of it. I donāt even have to remove atoms for this
to be a problem. All I have to do try to define which atoms
here are part of the chair and which arenāt. At the atomic level, there isnāt a definite
boundary. Near the edge, it will hard to tell whether
a particular molecule is part of the moisture in the chair or part of the ambient humidity. Instead of there being a single chair here,
it seems like REALLY there are billions and billions of candidates for the chair. Which one is the chair? But now, suppose that instead of removing
pieces like in a sorities sequences or choosing pieces like in the problem of the many, we
instead discard pieces and replace them with new, similar pieces. This is the set up to the famous SHIP OF THESEUS
paradox. Suppose I buy a boat and name it THESEUS. Over time, parts of the boat wear out and
I replace them with brand new parts. After, say 10 years, I might realize that
not a single part of my boat was part of the boat on the day I bought it. Do I now own a different boat? Have I owned TWO boats? But now suppose the someone has been following
me all these years and has been picking up each old part I throw out and storing them
in a warehouse. After I replaced all the original parts they
take them and join them back the way they way there were 10 years ago. Which boat is THESEUS? Both? If we conclude that ordinary objects donāt
exist, the problems of sorites, the many, theseus, over-determination, and over-counting
all evaporate. If there are only simples and they never compose
anything, then which one is the ship of theseus is easy to answer: neither! Neither are the boat and nothing ever was
the boat. All that happened was that some simples got
moved around. The simples the scavenger has are the simples
I possessed when I bought the boat, but thereās no mystery of persistence: removing or exchanging
a piece of stuff never left me with the same stuff. Thereās no mystery as to which of the billions
of chair candidates here is THE chair and the removal of no specific atoms will ever
stop it from being a chair because it there is no chair here and there never was. There are only simples arranged chair-wise. The illusion that there ARE composites
that can survive changes in parts is an artifact of our minds. Itās a helpful one that allows us to track
certain properties and ignore others, but when taken seriously, it obviously isnāt
really how the universe works. And thatās okay. We shouldnāt be embarassed when we talk
about boats or chairs. Our words for ordinary objects really do refer
to actual phenomena and therefore are more correct than believing that, say, the sun
turned into a black hole yesterday. Unlike the false statement that chairs exist,
there is NO evidence saying the sun turned into a black hole yesterday could even be
INCORRECTLY describing. Because of this, Trenton Merricks calls the
belief in ordinary objects false but, ānearly as good as true.ā This is all silly, though, right? Of course there are chairs. If you believe that there are some simples
arranged chair-wise, then you admit that thereās a chair! Because thatās just what a chair IS. Itās not some additional THING over-and-above
these simples: it just IS them. Each is still an atom or electron or whatever,
but TOGETHER they are a chair. Not so fast there, chair-lover. What do you MEAN āa chair IS simples arranged
chair-wise?ā the phrase āsimples arranged chair-wiseā
just picks out these simples. Thereās nothing else for that phrase to
refer to. There arenāt all of these simples and then
ALSO some OTHER simples that are the simples arranged chair-wise. So do you mean that āchairā is a disguised
plural? That it refers to lots of things like the
phrase āthese booksā? Because āthese booksā only commits us
to the existence of this book and this book but not an additional single
object thatās called a āthese books.ā Likewise, if āchairā just means this simple
and this simple and this simple, then it points to a whole bunch of things and not one of
them is a chair. Sure, āchairsā exist if by chair we mean
a word for all these simples. But if by chair we mean an actual object in
the universe, there just arenāt any, my friend. Exceptā¦ maybe there is no chair over-and-above
the simples, but instead something happens when an assortment of simples are arranged
into a chair-shape. Each member continues to be a single atom
or whatever, but COLLECTIVELY they all simultaneously BECOME one thing: a chair. Okay, so then either thereās no chair here,
just simples; or somehow a miraculous contradiction has appeared: many things and ALSO one thing
that, despite both clearly differing in that respect, are still identical! It looks like chairs canāt be identical
to the parts theyāre supposedly composed of.. but chairs also canāt be DIFFERENT from
their composite parts because thereās nothing else there and, after counting and accounting
for their parts, thereās nothing left for the existence of a chair to cause or explain. To rescue chairs from non-existence, we need
to find a way to show that a chair is independent of its atoms ā and therefore distinct from
them ā but not SO distinct that itās impossibly over-and-above them. We need to find a way to make chairs ONTOLOGICALLY
INNOCENT. To have our cake and not have it, too. Amie Thomasson does this in a very clever
way. She points out that if I ask you, āhey,
is there anything in the fridge?ā and you open it, see thatās it empty, and say, āthereās
nothing in hereā it would be weird if I came over, looked inside, found a single eyelash
in the corner and said, āummm EXCUSE me? What is this?! you said there was no THING
in the fridge, but there was an eyelash and, gosh dangit, the whole things is actually
FULL! Of AIR.ā That would be weird because when I asked if
there was anything in the fridge, it was implied that I meant anything TO EAT. By arguing that the empty fridge is not REALLY
empty, I was using the word āthingā in what Thomasson calls a āneutral sense.ā I used it to mean any and all entities that
could possibly be described. But you took me to be using āthingā in
what she calls a āsortalā sense. A sortal is a term that tells us what a thing
is in way that allows us to count how many there are AND know when there is or isnāt
one. āWaterā is not a sortal. If I told you there was water in my basement
and you asked, āhow many waters?ā Iād have to use a sortal to answer you. For example, āgallons of water.ā Thomasson argues that the neutral use of āthingā
is meaningless when used to ask questions. For example, if I used thing in a neutral sense and asked how many orange things are in this video you would have no idea how I wanted you to carve it all up thus, there would be no would be no single correct answer. You might say, "uh, one orange thing? Your shirt?" But then I could say, āwhat, no there's my left sleeve, my right sleeve, the inside of the shirt, the outside of the shirt. Come on, there's way more than one." Unless we use a sortal net, any search for
what things there are will end in confusion. Not because there are no things, but because
it hasnāt been made clear what conditions to apply when searching. For Thomasson, this means that what we find
depends on what APPLICATION CONDITIONS we use. If I ask if thereās anything here that the
condition āsmaller than a moleculeā applies to, you could note each such thing and give
me an inventory. āChairā would not be on the list. But if I asked you if there were any medium-sized
rigid-acording-to human strength things here, āchairā would probably go on your list,
and no single atom would. If an application condition is satisfied in
the wrold, then the thing is descrbes exists. So CHAIRS do exist. If the application conditions for one thing
are also sufficient for something else, then, if we find the first thing, we have found
the other because itās existence is entailed ANLYTICALLY by the existence of the first
thing ā that is, by meaning and logic alone. For example, if I say that I live in a house
you can conclude ā without looking! ā that I live in a building. Thereās no paradox here, I donāt live
in a house AND a building ā two distinct things that defy the laws of physics by being
co-located. Instead, the conditions that apply to a house
are also sufficient for building. So a single chair is not impossibly identical
to some collection of many. Nor is it somehow over-and-above its parts. Instead, atoms arranged chair-wise merely
logically ENTAIL a chair. The entailment connects things differentiated
by distinct application conditions. When we ask which one is the ship of theseus,
a puzzle erupts because weāre being too neutral. We need to say what we mean by āship of
theseusā: if we mean the original parts, then this is it. Do we mean the thing registered to me by the
boat authorities? well then itās this one. āBut which is the REAL oneā is an incomplete
pseudoquestion. When it come to sorites sequences, I think
we need to just stipulate where the boundary is. I donāt think thereās an objective answer
provided by the universe or God as to exactly what is and isnāt a chair, but that doesnāt
HAVE to mean that there arenāt any chairs, it can just mean that every single collection
of simples is itās own unique object independent of our minds and that we get to decide which
we will call chairs. Vagueness comes from our minds and our language
but there are no vague objects in the universe. We donāt have to believe that our reality
is simulated, but I do think we have to believe that itās stipulated: it is a reality that
contains not what intelligent machines have decided to give us, but what we have decided
we have. Thereās no fact of the matter as to whether
calling this a star is the TRUE way to carve up this stuff. Itās a pretty useful way to do it, and helpful
for at least human purposes, but āSTARā is a thing WE imposed on the world. As Michael Jubien puts it, āthere are no
things, but as a consequence there are as many things as we like.ā As for the problem of the many, we can simply
just admit that there really are billions of slightly different chairs here. Some include a few boundary atoms that others
donāt, but since they all act and react pretty much in unison, in our daily lives
it doesnāt matter which exact material collection we mean when we say āthis chair.ā However, letās go back to our cranes. When we talked about holes we said that holes
might be ONTOLOGICALLY parasitic. That their existence seems to require the
existence of something ELSE: something that can HOST the hole. Perhaps this crane is holey, too. Not a physical thing in its own right, but
a disturbance IN some paper. There is no material crane here, there is
only some paper that is arranged crane-wise. But once we start entertaining that notion,
we realize that nearly EVERYTHING we see and feel all ordinary obejcts and even ourselves are ontological parasites Michael Jubien calls our tendency to think
that what is true of a āchairā is true of the material that is chairing OBJECT FIXATION
or PROPERTY REPRESSION. Object fixation is useful and ānearly as
good as trueā but when paradxoes loom, we should remember that while chairs exist, they
arenāt made out of matter and canāt be touched or or felt or tasted. All I can do is taste some stuff while it
chairs. If it looks like a duck, swims like a duck,
and quacks like a duck, then itās not a duck, but it is arranged duck-wise. I think that the only concrete physical things
in our universe are simples ā or, since our universe could be gunky ā the material
world only contains stuff. And yes, this stuff is chair-ing, but the
road paved by the idea that that makes this stuff A chair leads to paradox. To see how we could have made that mistake,
letās remember the famous Clintonian dictum that often āit depends on what the meaning
of āisā isā Thereās the āisā of predication, which
tells us what some thing is like, as in, this cheese IS floppy. And then thereās the āisā of identity
which tells us what is the same as what for example, 2+2 IS 4. To believe that chairs are made of matter
ā to be believe that YOU are made of matter ā is to confuse these two ISes. When a collection of properties are extremely
thorough in telling us what to expect from some stuff, we tend to just go ahead and NOUN
them: collapse them into a single word and believe it doesnāt just describe some stuff,
but REFERS to it. I think we have an intuitive sense of the
thoroughness of properties and this can be seen in how we order our adjectives. āBigā can mean many things. A big diamond and big house are very different
in size. āBlueā tells me a bit more about what
to expect, but CHEESEBURGER, oooh thatās specific. So specific, in fact, that we call it a noun. This increasing thoroughness may be partly
responsible for the fact that ābig blue cheseburgerā sounds fine, but blue big cheeseburgerā
sounds kind of weird. When we embrace the idea that cheseburgers
are not physical objects, but instead, exist as an abstract set of properties like juicy,
warm, soft, and so on, the specter of ontolgical paradox dissipates. You and I are not physical objects either. āMichael-ingā is a bunch of different
properties and most of them are very vague. They include things like, āknowing who Kevin
is, being more or less a certain height, having a roughly continous relationship with the
stuff that Mcihaeled yesterday and that thatās Michael-ing todayā and so. Some of what it means to Michael does concern
composition, like, the fact that I will still exist even if I shave off the stuff I call
my beard. If I shaved off my beard, there would still
be some stuff Michael-ing, but it would be different stuff than before. Weāre able to lose parts and change and
grow because we arenāt made of matter, weāre hosted by matter. Thereās no thing that is you and no thing
that is ME. As Alan Watts would say, the universe doesnāt
contain people, the universe PEOPLES. Chairs and tables and rocks and buckets and people are not made of atoms, they are preformed by atoms. We are disturbances in stuff and none of it
is us. This stuff right here is not me. It's just me-ing. We are not the universe seeing itself, we
ARE the seeing. I am not a thing that dies and becomes scattered,
I AM death and I AM the scattering And
as always, thanks for watching. as always, links to read and learn more can be found in the description down below there's also a link down there to subscribe to the curiosity box if you subscribe now, this will be your first box but remember, use code BOGO and we'll you are summer box as well completely free give your brain a treat. support vsauce, support Alzheimer's research, and creators everywhere by joining today I'll see you there. And as always, thanks for watching.
Life has meaning again!!!
Doesn't everyone just sit on a table?
So... chairs don't exist, but existance chairs?
His psychosis can't be stopped. It's self-sustaining now.
I personally really enjoyed this episode, though I can understand that philosophical debate may not be as interesting to some people
The questions of existence posed in this video have existed for thousands of years, and while it may seem like a simple linguistic argument, the actual implications can be quite profound
Say what you want about this video but I think some people forget how popular vSauce actually is.
Yes nothing was new in this video for you or me, but for many people, questions about what is 'real' and what constitutes reality are not things they would like to ask themselves or think about in any great capacity. I think this video does a service by making topics like this more accessible to the general public that usually consumes shor and snappy anti-illectual content.
P.S. I think its made even more accessible by how Michael makes himself into a meme.
The video made me ponder this question: āare nouns just really descriptive adjectives?ā If nouns canāt exist then are they just describing something very specifically?
When philosophers try to do set theory
I kept waiting for him to launch into some out of left field tangent but no this really is a pure 37 minute discussion about if chairs exist.