The Philosophy of Science - Hilary Putnam & Bryan Magee (1978)

Video Statistics and Information

Video
Captions Word Cloud
Reddit Comments
Captions
The connection between philosophy  and the mathematical sciences has   always been very close. Plato had written  over the door of his academy the words,   "Let no one enter here who is ignorant of  geometry." It was Aristotle who codified   the basic sciences into the categories and  gave them the names that we use to this day.   Some of the greatest philosophers have been  themselves great mathematicians who invented   new branches of mathematics. Descartes is an  obvious example, and so is Leibniz and Pascal. In fact, most of the great philosophers, not all  but most, came to philosophy from mathematics or   the sciences. And this tendency is  continued into our present century. Bertrand Russell was trained  first as a mathematician,   Wittgenstein was trained first as an engineer. The reason for this persisting  connection is, I think, obvious.   And that is that the basic urge, which has  driven most of the greatest philosophers,   has been the urge to deepen our understanding  of the world and of its structure.   And this is also what  creative scientists are doing. For most of the past, too, people thought that  mathematics was the most indubitable knowledge,   as well as being utterly precise and clear, that  human beings possessed. So there have always been   plenty of philosophers examining mathematics to  try and find out what was so special about it, and   whether this was something that could be applied  to the acquisition of other sorts of knowledge.   Ditto with the sciences, which were also  thought to yield a very specially safe   and certain kind of knowledge. What was it about science that  made its results so reliable,   people asked themselves. And could its methods,  whatever these were, be used in other fields? These investigations into the concepts, and  methods, and procedures, and models that are   involved in mathematics and in science have come  to be known as the philosophy of mathematics   and the philosophy of science. And it's with these  that we're going to be concerned in this program. Chiefly with the philosophy of science,  though, in fact, we have someone taking   part who is expert in both -- Professor  Hilary Putnam of Harvard University. Professor Putnam, I'd like to start our discussion  from a standpoint which I think a very large   number of our viewers occupy anyway. And it's  really this. Since the 17th century, I suppose,   there's been a spectacular decline in religious  belief, especially in the West, and especially   among educated people. And for millions, the  role that used to be taken in life by a world   view based on religion has been increasingly  supplanting by a world view based on science or,   at least, purporting to be derived from science,  anyway. And this is still enormously powerful,   and the hold that it has on people's minds  throughout the West probably affects all of us. So I think I'd like to start this  discussion by getting you to pin   down that scientific world outlook which  is so influential in the modern world   and which will be underlying a lot of  what we're going to have to talk about. Let me dodge the question a little bit by talking  not about what scientists think now but what   many scientists thought 100  years ago, or 75 years ago. Think of doing a crossword puzzle. You might  have to change a few things as you go along.   But towards the end everything fits, and  things get added on one step at a time.   That's the way the progress of  science looked for 300 years. In 1900, a famous mathematician, David Hilbert,  gave a list of 50 mathematical problems to a world   congress of mathematicians, which are still very  famous. And it's very interesting that he included   one problem which we would not call a  mathematical problem, very early in the   list. I think it's problem 3, which was to put the  foundations of physics on a satisfactory basis. Just a small task. And that was for  mathematicians. Not for physicists. To tidy it up. That's right. The ideas is, Newton,  Maxwell, Dalton, and so on had all   put in all the parts of the story, and now it was  just for mathematicians to, basically, clean up   the logic, as it were. I think, in a conversation  we had a couple of days ago, you described this as   a treasure chest view and I like that picture.  Here's this big chest that we're just filling   up. It's an accumulation, and you don't have to  subtract, you don't have to take out. Occasionally   you make a little mistake, but basically  the idea is, when you shift the metaphor,   like building a pyramid. You put down the ground  floor, then the next floor, then the next floor.   It just goes up. That's part of it. The view  of knowledge as growing by accumulation. The other part of it is the idea that the special  success of the sciences -- and obviously what   we're impressed by is success. This culture values  success and science is a successful institution.   But there is the idea that science owes  its success to using a special method.   And that comes probably from history of science,  from the fact that Newton, for example, lived   after Bacon, was influenced by Bacon. And the idea  that empirical science has grown up together with   something called inductive logic. And this idea  that there's a method, the inductive method,   and that the sciences can be characterized by  the fact that they use this method and use it   explicitly and consciously as it were  -- not, unconsciously as maybe someone   who's learning cooking might be using it,  but pretty deliberately and explicitly. So I think that these two things -- the idea of  knowledge as growing by accumulation and growing   by the use of a special method, the inductive  method, are the key elements of the old view. Yes, and if I were going to put the same thing,  I suppose, slightly differently I think I'd say   this. For 200 or 300 years, educated Western man  thought of the universe, and everything in it as   consisting of matter in motion. And that was all  there was, whether from the outermost galaxies   of the stars into ourselves, and our bodies,  and the cells of which we made up, and so on. And science was finding out more and more about  this matter, and its structure, and its motion,   by a method which you just  characterized as the scientific method.   And the idea was that, if we went on long  enough, we'd simply -- as you said with the   crossword puzzle metaphor -- we'd find out  everything there was to find out. We could,   eventually, by scientific methods  completely explain and understand the world. Now, that has been abandoned by scientists,  hasn't it, though in fact this hasn't got through   yet to the non-scientists. There are still large  numbers of non-scientists who go on thinking   that that's how scientists think.  But of course they no longer do,   do they? I mean, this is starting to break down. I think it's started to break down. I think  it started to break down with Einstein.   If I can drag in a bit of history of philosophy,  screaming, by the hair, Kant did something in   philosophy which I think has begun to happen now  in science. He challenged a certain view of truth. Before Kant, no philosopher really doubted  that truth was simply correspondence to   reality. I mean, there are different words, some  philosophers spoke of agreement. But the idea is   a mirror theory of knowledge. Well, Kant said  it isn't so simple. There's a contribution of   the thinking mind. Sure, it isn't made up by  the mind. Kant was no idealist. It isn't all a   fiction. It isn't something we make up. But it  isn't just a copy, either. What we call truth   depends both on what there is, on the way things  are, and on the contribution of the thinker, the   mind. I think that today scientists have come to  a somewhat similar view. That since the beginning   of the 20th century, the idea that there's  a human contribution, a mental contribution,   to what we call truth, that theories aren't  simply dictated to us by the facts, as it were. I'd like to ask you to unpack that a little  because I think that some of our viewers will   find idea a little puzzling. How can it be, some  people will ask themselves, that what is and is   not true can depend not only on what the facts  are, but on the human mind? How can that be? Well, let me use an analogy with vision. We tend  to think that's what we see just depends on what's   out there. But the more one studies vision, either  as a scientist or as a painter, one discovers that   what's called vision involves an enormous amount  of interpretation. The color we see as red is   not the same color, in terms of wavelengths, at  different times of the day. So that even in what   we think of as our simplest transaction with the  world, just looking at it, we are interpreting. In other words we bring a whole number  of things to the world that we're not   directly conscious of, usually, unless  we turn inwards and start examining them. That's right. I think the world must've looked  different in the Middle Ages to someone who looked   up and thought of the stars as up and us at the  bottom, for example. Today, when we look out into   space, I think we have a different experience  than somebody with the medieval world view. And what you're saying is that  the very categories in which we   see the world and interpret  our experience, and the   ideas within which we organize our observations  and the facts around us and such, are provided   by us. So that the world as conceived by science  is partly contributed by external facts but also   partly contributed by categories and ways of  seeing things which come from the human observer. That's right. And an example of that  in science -- I'll oversimplify,   but it's not basically falsified -- is  this wave/particle business. It's not that   there's something, an electron,  which is somehow half a wave and   half a particle -- that would be meaningless --  but that there are many experiments which can   be described two ways. You can either think  of the electron as a wave, or you can think   of it as a particle. And both descriptions  are, in some crazy way, true and adequate. They're alternative ways of describing the  same fact, and both descriptions are accurate? That's right. Philosophies have started  talking of equivalent descriptions.   That's a term used in philosophy of science. But now, for a couple of hundred years after  Newton, educated Weston man thought that what   Newton had produced was objective fact, that he  had discovered laws which governed the workings   of the world and the workings of the universe.  And this was just objectively true independently   of us. That Newton and other scientists had read  these facts off of nature by observing it, and   looking at it, and so on. And these statements,  which made up science, were simply true. Now, there came, didn't there, a period in the  development of science, beginning in the late   19th century, when people began to realize that  these statements were not entirely true, that this   wasn't just a body of objective fact which had  been read off from the world. In other words, that   science was corrigible, scientific theories  could be wrong. And that raises some very   profound questions. I mean, if science isn't just  an objectively true description of the way things   are, what is it? And if we don't get it from  observing the world, where do we get it from? Well, I don't want to say we don't get  it from observing the world at all.   Obviously, part of this Kantian image is that  there is a contribution which is not us. There's   something out there. But that also there's a  contribution from us. And even Kant, by the way,   thought that Newtonian science was indubitable. in  fact he thought we contributed its indubitability.   The step beyond Kant is the idea that not only is  reality partly mind dependent, but that there are   alternatives, and that the concepts we impose on  the world may not be the right ones, and we may   have to change them. That there's an interaction  between what we contribute and what we find out. Now, what was it that made people begin to  realize that this basic conception of science   as objective truth was wrong, that science  was corrigible, that science was fallible? I think it's that the older science  turned out to be wrong where no one   expected it to be wrong, not in  detail, but in the big picture.   It's not that we find out that, say, the sun  isn't 93 million miles from the earth but only 20   million miles from the earth. That's not going to  happen. I mean, sometimes one makes blunders even   about things like that. But that's like making a  blunder about whether there's a chair in the room.   Wholesale skepticism about whether numerical  values are right in science would be   as unjustified as wholesale  skepticism about anything. But where the newer theories don't agree with  Newton is not over the approximate truth of   the mathematical expressions in Newton's theory.  Those are still perfectly good for calculation.   It's over the big picture. We've replaced the  picture of an absolute space and an absolute   time by the picture of a four dimensional space  time. We replaced a picture of a Euclidean world   by a picture of a world which obeys a  geometry Euclid never dreamed of. We've   swung back to the picture of the word as having  a beginning in time, which is really a shocker.   It's not even that things once  refuted stay refuted forever. So it means, really, that a whole conception of  science has been superseded. Instead of thinking   of science as a body of knowledge which is being  added to all the time by further scientific work,   that whole conception of science has in dispensed  with, really, hasn't it? And we now think of it   as a set of theories which are themselves  constantly being replaced by better theories,   by more accurate theories, by richer, more  explanatory theories. And even the theories   we now have, like those of Einstein and  his successors, will probably be replaced,   in the course of time, by other, better theories  by scientists yet unknown. Isn't that so? That's exactly right. In fact scientists  themselves make this prediction, that is,   that the main theories of the 20th century  -- relativity and quantum mechanics -- will   give way to some other theory which will  interpret both of them, and so on forever. Now, this raises a very fundamental question,  namely, the question, what is truth? I mean,   when we say that this or that scientific  statement is true, or this or that scientific   theory is true, what, in these newly understood  circumstances of ours, can we mean by truth? There's still two views that have been since Kant.  One is that this old correspondence view still has   its adherents. But I think the view that's  coming in more and more is that one cannot   make a total separation between what's true  and what our standards of assertibility are. That the way in which -- what I call  using the Kantian picture -- the   mind-dependence of truth comes in is the  fact that what's true and what's false   is in part a function of what our  standards of truth and falsity are. And that depends on our interests, which,  again, change over time, of course. That's right. I'd like you to say a little more about  this question of truth because this again,   I think, is puzzling to the layman. I  think that people who are not trained in   science or philosophy are apt to think  that there are a certain set of facts,   and a true statement is a statement  that accurately describes those facts.   I'd like to talk a little about some of the  difficulties that are actually involved in this. I think the biggest difficulty in science  itself comes from the fact that, even within   one scientific theory, you often find different  accounts can be given the so-called facts. This   came in with the special theory of relativity,  when it turned out that facts about simultaneity,   where the two things happen at the same  time, could be described differently by   different observers. One could say "Boy Scout  A fired a starter's pistol before Boy Scout B,"   the other could say, "No, Boy Scout B fired a  starter's pistol before Boy Scout A," and if the   distance is sufficiently large, so that a light  signal can't travel from one to the other without   exceeding the speed of light, then it may be both  descriptions are correct. Both are admissible. Of course, this leads to profound  conceptual difficulties in understanding   some modern scientific theories.  And this prompts the thought that   a scientific theory can be useful, and  meaningful, and can work even if nobody really   quite understands what it means. And this is the  case with quantum mechanics, isn't it? I mean,   nobody is really sure what quantum  mechanics actually means, and yet it works. That's right. And, again, I want to say, one  shouldn't push that too far, because I think   we don't want to give up our standards  of intelligibility altogether. We want   to say -- quantum mechanics works, and the very  fact that it works means that there's something   fundamentally right about it. And with respect  to its intelligibility, we're willing to say, in   part, that may be that we have the wrong standards  of intelligibility, that we have to change our   intuitions. But in part, there are real paradoxes  in the theory. And I think that's more work has   to be done to really get a satisfactory resolution  of these paradoxes. Things are very ticklish now. Yes, I think somebody hearing our discussion to  whom, perhaps, some of these ideas are new might   find himself thinking -- well, if all this is  so, how is it that science works? If traditional   scientific theories are breaking down, if science  is turning out not to be a body of reliable,   permanent, firm, objective knowledge, if a  significant portion of every scientific theory is   subjective anyway, in the sense that  it's contributed by the human mind,   by the observed by the scientists, how is it,  in these circumstances, that we can actually   build bridges, fly airplanes, make rockets  go to the moon, and actually make all this   soft fuzzy changing partly subjective body  of theory work for us. It must fit the world,   in some very basic way, in spite of  everything that we've been saying. That's true, but I think the contrast between  being subjective and fitting the world isn't   altogether right. I'm not saying that scientific  knowledge is subjective, or that anything goes.   I'm saying we're in the difficult position that  we often are in in life of thinking there is a   difference between good and bad reasoning, but we  don't have a mechanical rule. In everyday life,   we use interest-loaded terms. We wouldn't  say that there's a policeman on the corner   if we didn't have a whole network of social  institutions. Somebody coming from a primitive   tribe which didn't have policemen might say  there's a man in blue on the corner. But the   fact that the notion of a policeman is shaped  by our interests doesn't mean that it can't be   objectively true that there's a policeman  on the corner. Also, I think science works   precisely because of this corrigibility, in  large part, as Professor Poppers pointed out.   The difference between science and previous ways  of trying to find out truth is in large part   that scientists are willing to test their ideas  because they don't regard them as infallible,   in a way, that was known at the beginning,  and then in the success of Newtonian science,   somewhat forgotten. And we've had to be reminded  again of what Bacon knew -- that you have to put   questions to nature and be willing to  change your ideas if they don't work. In some respects, the traditional opposition  between science and religion -- the two parties   have crossed places, haven't they? I mean,  many religious people now believe they have   certain knowledge about the world, that  it was created by called a god, that he   made us in his own image, gave us immortal souls  which will survive out there, and so on. Certain   very fundamental propositions which they hold  with absolute certainty. And it's the scientist   who believes that everything is fallible, that  the world is a mysterious place that we'll never   get to the end of the mystery of, and so on  and so forth. Isn't there something in that? Maybe. You say it maybe? I'm not sure. You're not sure. Well, let's not pursue that. But one point I do want to take up with  you, leaving even religion aside, is that   now science is seen in this entirely  different way that you've been describing,   by virtually all scientists, doesn't it mean that  the difference between science and non-science   isn't what it was always thought of as being.  In other words, since science is so subjective,   indefinite, changing, and so on, it's no longer a  clearly-cut and different kind of human activity,   and kind of human knowledge, from other sorts of  human knowledge and other sorts of human activity. I think that's both true and culturally  very important. I think the harm that   the old picture of science does is that  if there is this realm of absolute fact   that scientists are gradually accumulating  then everything else appears, somehow,   as non-knowledge, something to which even  words like true and false can't properly apply. I think that the so-called fact-value dichotomy  is a very good example of this. It's hard to have   a discussion, on politics for example, without  someone very quickly say, at least in my country:   "is that a fact or a value judgment?" As though  it can't be a fact that Hitler was a bad man,   for example, or a factory that Farah  Fawcett Majors is a beautiful woman. And do you think that it is a  fact that Hitler was a bad man? Oh yes, I do. I do too. But then, if this is so, if we're abandoning  so many of these comfortable, clear-cut,   distinctions of the past, what's the  point of continuing to use the category,   or the notion or the term "science" anyway?  I mean, does it any longer clearly demarcate   something differentiable from everything else. I don't think it does. I think that if you're  going to distinguish science from non-science,   that makes a lot of sense if you still have this  old view that there's this inductive method. What   make something science is that it uses it and uses  it pretty consciously and pretty deliberately.   And that what makes something non-science  is, either it uses it entirety unconsciously,   as in learning how to cook -- you're not  consciously thinking about inductive logic,   or perhaps doesn't use it at all, as metaphysics  was alleged not to use it all, I think unfairly. But when you both say that there's a sharp line  between, say, practical knowledge and science.   And to say that the method which is  supposed to draw this line is rather fuzzy,   something that we can state exactly -- and  attempts to state it, by the way, have been   very much a failure, still.  Inductive logic cannot be, say,   programmed on a computer the way deductive  logic can be programmed on a computer. And I think the development of deductive logic  in the last 100 years and the development of the   computer have really brought very dramatically  just what a different state we are in   with respect to proof in the mathematical  sciences, which we can state rigorous canons for,   and proof in what used to be called the inductive  sciences, where we can state general maxims,   but you really have to use intuition,  general know-how, and so on in applying them. One of the two categories that you described the  old-fashioned way of looking at science in terms   of was that there was a particular scientific  method, that you observed the facts, and,   on the basis of these observed instances, you  generalized to form scientific theories which   you then verified by experiment,  and so on. That was the old view. Now that that has been abandoned, is  there any longer any single method   which is thought of as being scientific method? I don't think they should be. People talk of  scientific method as a sort of fiction. But   I think that, even in physics where you do get  experiments and tests which pretty much fit the   textbooks, there's a great deal that doesn't and  a great deal that shouldn't. And I think, in fact,   in the culture I don't really believe there's  an agreement on what a science and what isn't. Any university will tell you in its  catalog that there are things called   social sciences and that sociology is as  science, and that economics is a science.   I bet if you ask anyone in the physics department  whether sociology is a science, he'll say no. And why will he say no? That's interesting. I think the real reason is not that the  sociologists don't use the inductive   method. They probably use it more conscientiously,   poor things, than the physicists do. I think  it's because they're not as successful. So in other words, science has become almost  a name for successful pursuit of knowledge? That's right. Well now, I think you've given a very, very good  description of the way in which these age-old view   of what science was has broken down in our century  and been replaced by something much more fluid and   perhaps much more difficult to get hold of. But  you have, I think, described it very clearly. Can we now come, against, this background  to what philosophers of science are actually   doing. You are a philosopher of science.  What do you and your colleagues do? Well, part of what we do which I won't  try to describe on this broadcast is   fairly technical investigation  of specific scientific theories.   We look at quantum mechanics very closely, both to  learn what lessons we can from it for philosophy   and to see what contributions we can make as  philosophers to clarifying its foundations. We look at relativity theory very closely.  We look at Darwinian evolution very closely,   and so on. This is the part of philosophy of  science which provides the data for the rest.   But much philosophy of sciences  shades over into general philosophy. And I think that the best way to  describe it is in terms of what   we've been talking about. That is, each  of the issues we've been talking about   divides philosophers of science. There  are philosophers of science who have a   correspondence view of truth and try to  show that this can be made precise, that   the objections can be overcome, you can  still view science, somehow, in the old way. And there are others who try to sketch  what another view of truth would come to. There are philosophers who still think there  is an inductive method that can be rigorously   stated and who work on inductive logic. And by  the way, I think it's important there should be   because we won't make progress to trying to  state the inductive method if there aren't. And that there are others who view  the development of science more   culturally, more historically, and then people  like myself who are have a sort of in-between   position, that there's something to the notion  of a scientific method, there are clear examples,   but that it's more or less a continuum.  You mustn't think of it as a kind of   mechanical rule, an algorithm, that you  can apply to get scientific knowledge. So that I'd say each of these issues -- the nature  of truth, the nature of the scientific method,   whether there's any necessary truth in science,  any conceptual contribution which is permanent   and can't be subject to  revision is a big question. And who are you, plural, doing all this work  for? I don't ask that in an irreverent way,   but what I have in mind is this. I've myself  taken part in attempts to bring scientists and   philosophers together for discussions of precisely  the issues that you've raised. And these attempts   have usually failed and failed to the same reason,  namely, that the scientists lose interest. They go   back to their laboratories and get on with doing  more science. And the great bulk of scientists,   it seems to me, don't, in fact, take very much  of an interest in the issues that you've been   talking about. I think it's conspicuous that the  greatest of all scientists are exceptions. I mean,   the really block-busting, the path-breaking  scientists who've actually made the revolution   in this century that you've been talking about--  people like Einstein, Max Planck, Neils Bohr,   Max Born, Schrodinger, de Broglie, these people  were enormously interested in the conceptual   questions that's you've raised. But these were  the pioneering geniuses. And the great mass of   thousands of scientists, who follow on behind them  and put their work to its practical application,   they don't seem to care so who is listening to  you, who is reading the stuff that you publish? Well, I'd say, first of all, I  think we are basically writing   for the philosophically-interested  layman, for the reader of philosophy.   I don't view philosophy of science as giving  direct advice to scientists, just as I think   more philosophers are ill-advised to think  that they're giving, at least, immediately   current contemporary advice on how to live  your life or what bills to pass in parliament. On the other hand, I do think it's scientists tend  to know the philosophy of science of 50 years ago.   And perhaps this isn't a bad  thing. That is, perhaps this   time lag, this culture lag has some value in  weeding out what they shouldn't pay attention to. It's annoying to a philosopher   to encounter a scientist who's both sure that  he needn't listen to any philosophy of science,   and then who produces verbatim ideas which you can  recognize as coming from what was popular in 1928. Is there a direct parallel here between  what you're saying about scientists and   the economist Keynes' famous remark that  nearly all businessman who thought they   were indifferent to airy-fairy  economic theory were in fact the   slaves of the economic theorists of  yesterday, of a previous generation? That's exactly true. I suppose another parallel one  could make would be to say that the   account that ordinary language-users give  of language, and their use of language,   would be extremely unsophisticated simply because  they take it for granted and have never thought   about it. That too would probably apply to  the account that most scientists would give   of what they were doing when  they were doing their science. That's right. That is, it's a mistake  to think that merely because one   practices an activity one can give a theory of it. One criticism that's often been made about  philosopher of science is that although they   talk of science in this general way, what  they're nearly always referring to, in fact,   is one science namely physics. Now, it's true, isn't it, that the science  in which the most exciting developments have   probably taken place in the last 20 years,  anyway, has been not physics but biology. Are   philosophers of science open,  genuinely open, to the criticism   of being too physics-based in their view of  science and having ignored biology too much? I think I would defend us against that on  the grounds that I don't-- although the   theories in biology are of  great scientific importance--   Darwin's theory of evolution, Crick/Watson  on DNA, and so on they don't, by and large,   pose big methodological problems of a  kind of don't arise in physical science. I mean, I'm not sure whether  you're going to agree with that. Well, I mean, you mentioned evolution  just now. And it seems to me that here   is a concept which originated in one of  the sciences, namely biology, and which,   over a comparatively short period of time, has  spread throughout the whole of our culture.   So the way almost everybody think is influenced  by the notion of evolution. Not only about the   origins of man but about institutions, or  the arts, all kinds of other things. I mean,   evolution has become a dimension of Western man's  thinking about almost anything. Is that not so? That's right and perhaps there has not been enough  attention to this theory. Though what strikes   me as interesting is that the possibility of  explanations of what we think of as the biological   kind -- explanations in terms of function,  rather than in terms of physics and chemistry,   what you're made have come under more attention,  recently, as a result of computer science. Now, this does raise something  I'm particularly interested in   when you talk of computer Science And that is the  interaction between our technology, in the case   of computers, and philosophy. Not just science  and philosophy, but technology and philosophy. I mean, computers were originally constructed  on the basis of a self-conscious analogy with   the human mind. But as they became more  and more sophisticated we began to learn   things from them about the human mind. So  our construction of computers and what they,   then, tell us about ourselves seems to actually  proceed by interactive growth. Isn't that so? That's right, and today this is one are,  by the way, in which philosophers are in   close contact with scientists. That is, the  fields of linguistics, cognitive psychology,   computer science, philosophy of language, today,  interact constantly. People send papers to one   another -- not because someone tells them to.  There are conferences at which specialists needs   to meet together -- again, not because someone  decided there should be some cross-fertilization. The interesting thing about the computer  case, if I can stick with it for a moment, is,   one might have thought that the rise of the  computer would encourage a certain kind of   vulgar materialism. That is, "so, after all, we  are machines. So, after all, everything about   us can be explained in terms of physics and  chemistry." Paradoxically the real effect of   the computer on psychology on philosophy of mind  has been a decrease in that kind of reductionism. See, the thing about the computer is  that when you work with computers you   very rarely have to think about  their physics and chemistry. There's a distinction that people draw between  their software -- meaning their program, their   instructions, their rules, the way they do things  -- and their hardware. And generally, you ignore   their hardware. You talk about computers at the  software level. And you wouldn't really be able   to explain what they do, in a way that would be if  any use to anyone, in terms at the hardware level. There is a kind of emergence here, although  it's not a mystical kind of emergence,   it's not that they're violating the laws of  physics. It's just that the level of organization,   that higher-level facts about organization  have a kind of autonomy. You'd say this,   the fact that it's following this program explains  why does this, and I don't need to know how it's   built. I only need to know it can be built  in such a way that will follow this program. If you apply this to the mind, it  suggests a return to view of mind   that I associate with Aristotle. It's the  view that we are not ghosts in a machine,   not spirits which only temporarily in  bodies, but that the relation between   the mind in the body is a relation of  function to what has that function. Aristotle said, "if you use the word soul in  connection with an axe-- and of course," he said,   "you don't-- you'd say the soul of  an axe is cutting." And he said,   "the soul of the eye is seeing." And he  thought of man as "a thing that thinks." You're talking now of the alternative  to materialism and, say, a religious   view that this gives us puts me in mind,  instantly, of the most significant of   all the materialist philosophers in the modern  world, namely Marxism, which, after all, is the   official state philosophy of about  a third of mankind as we sit here   discussing this. Marxism claims to be scientific,  and this is a very important thing about it.   Is there a significant Marxist  contribution to the philosophy of science? I don't think there's a significant Marxist  contribution. But I don't think that the Marxist   were all wrong either. I think Engles was one  of the most scientifically learned men of his   century. He got a number of things wrong. But  he had an immense general scientific knowledge. And Anti-Duhring, his big book on philosophy  of science -- although it contains some rather   strange ideas, some of which he gets from Hegel,  by the way -- is, on the whole, a sensible book   on philosophy of science, among other things. On  the other hand, it's not specifically Marxist.   I'd say that Engles views on philosophy of  science are, in large part, influenced by   the standard philosophy of science of the time.  They're a fairly sophisticated inductive account. And what about subsequent  Marxist thinkers who also   had some pretension to be  philosophers, like Lenin, for example? Well, I think they're uneven.  Lenin, I think, is one of the worst.   He says, for example, that theories are copies  of motion. And there you have the copy theory, of   science just copying off the  reality, in its crudest view. Mao is more sophisticated. Mao  is very influenced by John Dewey,   who was widely read in China in the 1920s. Do you think it's actually made contribution  to the subject as it is today, or not really? I think that it anticipated -- it  perhaps might have made a contribution if   people have been less ideologically divided,  because I think non-Marx's could have learned:   the Marxists were among the first people to try  to, somehow, combine a realist view with a stress   on practice, with the stress on corrigibility.  And they were very hostile to the notion a priori   truth. And today many mainline philosophers  of science are very hostile to a priori truth. As it is, they play some of the role in philosophy  of science, I think, that Keynes said they play   in economics. He described Marx as one of  his, sort of, underground predecessors. When I was introducing this program I mentioned  not only the philosophy of science but also the   philosophy of mathematics. And before we close, I  would like us to say something about that anyway. I suppose one can really say that the central  problem in the philosophy of mathematics is a   direct parallel to the central problem  in the philosophy of science, namely,   how long does it fit the world?  With science it's how does science   fit the world? In mathematics it's how does  mathematics fit the world. is that right? That's right. And it's even worse,  because if you're trying to defend a   copy view, a correspondence of view of  truth in empirical science, you can answer   the question- - well how do we build up this  picture in such a way that it corresponds -- by   saying we have sense organs. As I mentioned  before that's not a total answer because   there's a tremendous amount of interpretation  involved in simple seeing and simple hearing. But if you are talking about numbers and sets,   and somebody says, okay, if mathematical knowledge  is simply some kind of a copy of the way numbers   are, and the way sets are, and the way other  abstract objects that mathematicians study are,   the question then, what sense  enables us to see how they? Yes, what is a number? A deeply problematic  question, but still an important one. That's right. And on the other hand, I don't  want to say that the anti-correspondence has   it very easy either. It seems to me that  mathematical knowledge is a real puzzle.   And I think that philosophers should concentrate  more on philosophy of mathematics than they do now   because it seems to be an area  where no theory works very well. Isn't there another very important parallel  between mathematics and science? I mean,   throughout the history of science one of the  conflicts has been between one camp who thought   that it was all about objects in the world  which existed independent of human experience   and another camp which thought, no, it's  human beings and observers who actually   contribute most of this. And as you  pointed out much earlier discussion,   the truth is almost certainly  a combination of both. There is a longstanding dispute in mathematics,  isn't there, between one body of people who   think that mathematical knowledge is something  that's, so to speak, inherent in the structure   of the world, and we derive it from the world by  experience and observation, and another body of   mathematical thought that says-- no, no, no,  mathematics is a creation of the human mind   which we then try to impose on reality like a  grid, as it was, on a landscape. Isn't that so? That's right. The latter story's attractive  because of the sense organ problem, but it   doesn't seem to work either because it seems  that we're not free to impose any mathematics or   any logic we want. Almost anyone would admit  that, at least, you have to be consistent.   And what's consistent and what isn't isn't  somehow something we can just make up or decide. When we try to stress conventionalist accounts,   subjective accounts, we come up against the  objectivity of mathematics. When we try to   stress the objectivity of mathematics we  come up against another set of problems. I think we can learn a lot more than  we now know about human knowledge and   about scientific knowledge by  going further into this area. Talking of where we're going from where  we are, so to speak, I think the most   interesting way in which you could end this  discussion, Professor Putnam, would be by   talking about what you regard as the most  interesting problem areas of the moment,   and therefore, I take it, the most-likely growth  area for the immediate future in both of the   subjects we've been discussing -- philosophy  of science and philosophy of mathematics. OK, I think that if I'm allowed to confine my  prediction to the immediate future -- because   we know that long-run predictions are always  false. But in the immediate future, I would expect   philosophy of mathematics to be a growth area, and  philosophy of logic. I would expect philosophy of   physics, I think, to decline somewhat from  its central place in philosophy of science. Although I think that part of it touches  philosophy of logic. The astounding suggestion has   actually come forward in connection with quantum  mechanics that we may have to change our logic,   our view of what the true logical laws are in  order to really understand how the world can be   quantum mechanical. I think this side a philosophy  of quantum mechanics that touches philosophy of   logic will be a hot discussion area. But more  generally, I think areas which we almost don't   think of this philosophy of science, that become  philosophy of language and philosophy of mind,   like these questions about computer models  of the mind, computer models of language,   and these more general questions about  theories of truth, the nature of truth,   the nature of verification, how science can be  objective even though there's not a rigorous   scientific method -- I think these questions  will continue to be the staples of the field. One thing that worries me about this whole area  is its relationship to the educated layman which,   in a sense, is the person our discussion has been  for. After all, it's not over the 70 years since   the 25-year-old Einstein published the theory of  relativity. And I'm sure you agree with me that   it's true to say now that the great majority  of educating people with higher education,   university degrees and so on, still have  scarcely any idea of what this is all about.   And it's done very little to actually  influence their view of the world. Isn't there a danger that now science and  mathematics are simply racing ahead, and the whole   new range and world of insight that it's giving  us into the universe in which we live simply   isn't filtering through to the non-specialist or  not filtering through anything like fast enough? That is a danger, but it's one  that something can be done about.   There's now, for example, a text of special  relativity, called space time physics,   which is designed for the first month of the first  freshman college physics course. And the authors   say, at the beginning, that they look forward to  the time when it will be taught in high schools. And do think that time will,  in fact, come, and quite soon? Oh, I'm sure of it. Yes, well, I think you're right.  And indeed, I hope you are. Thank you very much Professor Putnam.
Info
Channel: Philosophy Overdose
Views: 23,571
Rating: undefined out of 5
Keywords: History of Philosophy, Epistemology, Ontology, Analytic Philosophy, Philosophy Overdose, Metaphysics, Social Philosophy, Western Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Science, Hilary Putnam, Bryan Magee, Theory of Knowledge, Induction, Deduction, Logic, Fact-Value, Subjectivity, Objectivity, Scientific Method, Social Science, Positivism, Demarcation Problem, Inductive Logic, Correspondence Theory, Kant, Philosophy of Mathematics, Scientific Realism, The Nature of Truth, Philosophy, Materialism
Id: JJB2q8ufAgk
Channel Id: undefined
Length: 43min 52sec (2632 seconds)
Published: Sat Mar 26 2022
Related Videos
Note
Please note that this website is currently a work in progress! Lots of interesting data and statistics to come.