John Searle on the Philosophy of Language (1977) زیرنویس فارسی

Video Statistics and Information

Video
Captions Word Cloud
Reddit Comments
Captions
Bertrand Russell once said that until the second decade of this century-- and remember that, by that time, he was in his forties and had done virtually all the philosophical work for which he's really distinguished-- he regarded language as transparent. That's to say, as a medium, he could simply use without paying particular attention to it. Much the same must be true, I think, not only of other philosophers, but of writers of every kind-- novelists, poets, and so on. It's only in this century that the enormous self-consciousness of language, which we now take for granted, has developed. In fact, it's become one of the most prominent intellectual characteristics of our age. What's involved isn't just a superficial interest in words, but beliefs about absolutely fundamental matters. For instance, it's come to be widely believed that it's, more than anything else, the particular power of abstract thinking, made possible to us by language, that enables us to conceptualize a cope with innumerable aspects of reality which are not present to us, and thus relate ourselves to the world in the way we do. Many believe that it's this more than anything else that differentiates us from the animals. And for all these reasons, many believe that it's through the acquisition of a language that we become selves. If many of these things are true, then language is fundamental to our humanity and our individuality in ways that were not dreamt of til comparatively recently. And this, I think, is the underlying reason why philosophers have newly come to take such a powerful and, indeed, passionate interest in language. A philosopher of language who has made a reputation on both sides of the Atlantic is the American John Searle. He first started philosophy at Oxford, where he arrived as a Rhodes Scholar in the early 1950s. And he taught at Oxford for some years before returning to the United States. His book called Speech Acts, published in 1969, is something of a recent classic. He's now a professor of philosophy at the University of California in Berkeley. Professor Searle, there's one thing which I think we must get straight right at the beginning. I've been talking about the philosophy of language. But there is another phrase, "linguistic philosophy" or "linguistic analysis," which means something quite different. And this could be very confusing to our viewers unless we make the distinction clear at the outset. Yes, well, it can be made very simply. "Linguistic philosophy" and "linguistic analysis" are names techniques or methods for solving philosophical problems. The philosophy of language is not the name of a technique, but the name of a subject matter, branch of philosophy. I'll give you a couple of examples. The linguistic philosopher believes that you can solve certain traditional problems, such as problems about skepticism, by examining the ordinary use of words such as "know." You examine the use-- Know, know-- K-N-O-W. K-N-O-W-- verbs like "know," "believe," "suppose," "guess." Now, that would be a problem that the linguistic philosopher would work on. The philosophy of language is the name of a subject matter within philosophy. And there, the problems are such things as how do words relate to reality? What is the nature of meaning? What is truth, reference, logical necessity? Those are problems in the subject matter of the philosophy of language. Now, obviously, philosophers of language like yourself regard language as being absolutely fundamental to human life and human thought and so on. I tried to explain just now in my introduction to this discussion some of the reasons why, but I think it would be especially interesting to hear from you, as a professional in the field, your reasons for regarding language as being as central as you clearly do regard it as being. Well, I think to begin with, it's almost bound to be central to philosophy. Philosophy is, in an important sense, a conceptual inquiry. But quite apart from philosophy, I think language is crucial, for some of the reasons you were suggesting, crucial to an understanding of human beings and human life. We tend, in a pre-theoretical way, to have the idea that words are, as you said, transparent-- quoting Russell-- and that we can just apply them. We just name our experiences and our social relations. But in fact, when we began to investigate, what I think we find is that those forms of experience and those forms of social relations that we regard as characteristically human would be impossible without language, that language really is what distinguishes us more than anything else from other forms of animal life. I'll give you a couple of examples. Wittgenstein gave a very simple example to illustrate this about experience. It might seem obvious that our experience has just come to us independently of any language. But what Wittgenstein pointed out was a great many of our experiences would be impossible without language and gives this example. He draws a triangle. And he says, now see this as apex and that as base. And then he says, now see that as apex and that as base. And you'll find you have a different experience. I've named two different experiences that you can have. But the interesting thing is, they're not experiences my dog can have, not because he hasn't got the optical apparatus, but because he hasn't got the conceptual apparatus. The words, we want to say, are part of the experience. Now, that's a trivial example. And one can give lots of more grand examples. I mean, just take the following. La Rochefoucauld said-- I forget where-- that very few people would fall in love if they never read about it. And I think there is a real underlying truth in that and that is that categories like love and hate themselves influence the experiences, that our concepts determine or at least shape our experiences, that it would be impossible to have the experiences that we have without the linguistic categories we have. In other words, our experience of the world doesn't consist of the world as a lot of independent objects to which we as human beings then attach the labels of name, i.e. Words. What you're saying is the objects don't exist separately from words, that the words enter into the very structure of our experience. Yes, now let me see if I can say what I think you're driving at. It would be this-- not that language makes the world. That's the kind of subjectivism that I wouldn't want to accept, but rather something like this. What counts as an object, what counts as reality is a function of the system of representation that we bring to bear on reality, namely language. So the world doesn't come to us all sliced up into objects and experiences. What counts as this object or the same object or as a book or a table or a glass, that is a matter of the categories that we impose on the world. And those are linguistic. Would you say this is true of, say, an everyday object? Now, I'm holding here a glass of water. And I'm having the simple experience of seeing a glass of water. Now, for me to have the experience of seeing a glass of water, it's not enough for me simply to be having certain visual data. I've also got to have the concept "glass" and the concept "water." Precisely. And I've got to be able to locate this experience as coming under that concept. And, therefore, I couldn't have the experience of seeing a glass of water without some linguistic equipment. That's the point I'm making, precisely that. And, therefore, the language that we have helps to create the very categories in which we experience the world-- the very categories in which we see objects has language built into them, is what you're saying. It's precisely that. Therefore, by investigations in the philosophy of language, we are investigating the very structure of experience and the structure of whole ways of life and ways of viewing the world and so on. And, indeed, that was one of Wittgenstein's great themes, was the idea that a language is a form of life and that we should think of language as inner-penetrating with our life, not as something that stands outside and pictures it, as he once thought. Now, another thing I said in my introduction to this was that this enormous self-consciousness about the use of language is something that characterizes this century. It's very striking that something that is similar is true of the arts as well. For example, in this century, an enormous amount of poetry is being written about the writing of poetry or about how difficult it is to be a poet. We have filmmakers making films about the making of a film. And it's true of plays. And painting has, so to speak, exhibited it's own techniques. Even musical composition exhibits its own techniques. Art has become its own subject matter. The medium has itself become the object of attention. Now, there's a obvious parallel there with what has happened with language and philosophy. Do you think that these developments are all interconnected? Or do you think it's sheer coincidence? It surely is not sheer coincidence. I mean, I think there are certain features of the 20th century mode of sensibility that makes language seem immensely problematic to us. But let me disagree with one thing you've said. It isn't that philosophers have suddenly discovered language in the 20th century. There's a lot about language in-- Locke devoted a whole book of the Essay to it. There's a theory of language in Hume. And indeed, back to Plato and the Theaetetus there are theories of language. So it isn't something we've recently discovered. But the point I think you're making-- and I entirely agree with it-- is that language has come to seem problematic. It has come to seem-- to use your quotation from Russell-- not a matter of transparency. It isn't something that we can see right through to the world. It is itself a problem. And I think that has a great deal to do with something like the tremendous loss of confidence, the decline of rationality that occurred at the end of the 19th century. One doesn't know quite how to date the rise of modernism. But it is part of modernism in the arts. And surely, I can't, as you say-- it can't be just coincidental that the same awareness of the complexity and the problematic character of language exists in philosophy. Contrast Mill with the later Wittgenstein. And I think you see the break that I'm talking about now. You're stressing then that self-consciousness about language, in fact, goes back quite a long way in philosophy, probably further than it does in the arts with poetry and so on. Now, what were the specifically philosophical developments that brought it to a head in this century in the way that it did. Right, right. Well, now, that is a marvelously complicated subject. And let me pick out a couple of strands in that. First of all, there's a historical development. Descartes, over three centuries ago, asked this basic question in philosophy-- what is knowledge? How is knowledge possible? And I think if you take that question very seriously-- and we have in philosophy. That has been the central question for the centuries after Descartes. Eventually, that leads you to what will, I think, almost inevitably seem a more fundamental question-- namely, how does our mind represent the world at all? The question of what is meaning has come to seem prior to the question, what is knowledge. And there's certain other historical, certain specific historical features that led to that. Particularly, I would say the work of Frege in the 19th century, the German philosopher and mathematician, and the work of Russell in the early 20th century. And both of them were engaged in an investigation of the foundations of mathematics and the nature of mathematical knowledge. And they were led to develop certain theories about the nature of linguistic representation. In order to answer questions about the nature of mathematics and what goes on in mathematical statements, they were led to fundamental questions about the nature of statement making. Well, how? I mean, what is the connection between mathematical knowledge-- which would seem to be purely abstract and carried out in Greek symbols and such-- what is the connection between that and ordinary statements of the kind that philosophers now analyze. Well, there are numerous connections. But one basic connection was, what is the nature of mathematical truth? And both Frege and Russell argued that mathematics was really an extension of logic, that the statements of mathematics were true, in a sense, by definition. And in order to develop that, they needed a theory of truth and a theory of logic. And already now, we're in the philosophy of language when they began to develop that. So in other words, it's investigation into truth which develops into a investigation into meaning and, hence, an analysis of statements, sentences, and so on. Historically, I think it went that way. How did we get from Russell at the turn of the century to now? I think we can identify several lines of development. And oddly enough, Wittgenstein tends to play a crucial role in more than one of them. There's one line of development that goes from early Wittgenstein through the logical positivists like Carnap-- and I think one would include Russell's work in this line as well-- up to the present day and the works of philosophers like Quine and Davidson. Now, that line is mostly concerned with the relationship between meaning and truth. And the crucial question tends to be, what are the true conditions of an utterance? They are mostly concerned with conditions for establishing or determining the truth of sentences. And, obviously, this line will be more closely connected with the philosophy of science. Now, another line, which is the later Wittgenstein, and also the work of philosophers like Austin and Grice-- and I think I would include myself in this-- is more concerned with questions of linguistic use, with language seen as a part of human behavior. And the crucial question there is not what is the relation between meaning and truth, but what is the relation between meaning and use or meaning and the intentions with which a speaker makes an utterance? Now, those are two lines that I see developing. And I don't want to give you the impression that they're completely independent. No, they overlap and intertwine and interact in all sorts of ways. But then there's the third line that has come to seem very prominent in recent years. And that is the science of linguistics of which-- and Chomsky's name is the most prominent among contemporary linguists-- has come to interact with philosophy in ways that were not the case until really quite recently, until after 1957. You've made so many important points at once, Professor Searle, that I think it will be helpful if I sort of, so to speak, recapitulate before we start moving ahead. We're considering language, this amazing phenomenon of words and utterances and noises that is so fundamental to our humanity and to the way we cope with life and see the world and everything. Now, you might say there are two main ends to this process. There is the relationship of language to the world, the relationship of language to its objects, to all the things in the world that we talk about. And there is also the relationship of language to the language user. So this gives, as it were, two lines of development in the history of the subject we are considering. One lot of people have concentrated on discussing the relationship of words to their objects. And what that leads them to do is to analyze sentences and statements. It leads them to consider, above all else, the, question of under what conditions can statements be said to be true or false. And that leads them to develop formal criteria of truth and so on. That's one line of development that you mentioned. And you named Russell, the early Wittgenstein, Carnap, and Davidson as being the main-- And Quine. --and Quine, of course, yes. Now, the other line of development is interestingly different from that. That considers the subjects of language, not the objects of language-- in other words, the human beings using language. And the questions there are about their intentions. What are they using language for? What are their purposes? Well, now, you didn't say who the main people in that line of development were. But I-- No, I did-- a later Wittgenstein, Austin, and I would include [? Grice, ?] and Strawson, and other people as well. Yes, yes. And so those are the two main lines of development of the philosophy of language. And then as a sort of third, you threw in Chomsky in linguistics. I didn't throw it in. It comes charging in. It comes charging in. Well, now, right. Now, we've got that sketch map of the field. Is Now, for clarity's sake, let's take these one at a time. Now, let's start by discussing the school of thought that is interested in the relationship between language and its objects-- in other words, to use the most famous phrase, words and things. Can you unpack that a little? Well, let me-- should I do it by way of telling you something about the central figures? I think perhaps that's one way to go about it. Yes, yeah. Well, an epoch-making book in this field is Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. And he there articulates a very powerful theory of language, that sentences consistent, for him, as-- it consists of being, in effect, pictures. They are conventionalized pictures of facts, not that they actually look like the fact but that the relation between the way a sentence represents and the way a picture represents is structurally quite close. And then this picture theory of meaning, as it was called, formed the basis of his theory of language. Now, he came to reject that later. But that had a powerful influence-- his book the Tractatus had a powerful influence on a school of philosophers who were known as the logical positivists. And their center was in Vienna between the wars. And they, I think at least partly misunderstanding Wittgenstein, took the question of verification, how do we verify a proposition as the central question in meaning. And their slogan was called the verification principle. And the question that they asked, the crucial question was in order to know what a sentence means, what must we do to find out whether or not it's true. This was one way of putting the claim that the meaning of a statement is its method of verification. And they accepted the idea that all statements are either analytic or synthetic. Leading figure in this group, and perhaps the leading figure, is Carnap. And Carnap, though his views changed a great deal over the years, I think is primarily famous for this conception of language-- that is, that language primarily consists in statements that are true or false and that their meaning is intimately connected with their method of verification in such a way that we can define meaning in terms of verification. Now then, when we get to more recent times, when we get to Quine, Quine is most famous, his single most famous work was an attack on the analytic-synthetic distinction. That is, he attacks the idea that we can make clear distinction between that truth which is in virtue of meaning and that which is in virtue of matters of fact. And this then lead in his more recent work to what I can only describe as a general rejection of the notion of meaning. Quine adopts a behavioristic conception of language. He sees us as beings who are bombarded by stimuli, verbal and otherwise. And then we make verbal responses. And all that really amounts to meaning is our dispositions to respond verbally. There isn't, in addition to these dispositions to verbal responses, anything called meanings going through our mind. So Quine's behaviorism is closely connected with his empiricism. But ironically, it led him to reject what had seemed one of the foundation stones of a earlier generation of empiricists, namely the distinction between analytic and synthetic proposition. His famous article is called "Two Dogmas of Empiricism." " Am I going too fast through these or you want to-- No, no. Shall I go on to Davidson, then? Yes, Davidson is the one person you mentioned that you haven't talked about. Now, Davidson incidentally is remarkably influential in England and, indeed, I would say more influential in England than he is in his home country, but for what perhaps is a very good reason. He's certainly a very powerful philosopher. Davidson argues that there is a more intimate connection between meaning and truth than previous philosophers have been aware of or least have made explicit. And that is this. If we wanted a theory of meaning for a language, the way to get that theory of meaning would be to get a set of principles which would enable us to deduce for any sentence of the language under what conditions it was true, so that, for Davidson, a theory of truth really is a theory of meaning. There isn't any gulf between meaning and truth there in that once we've got a theory that makes clear what are the truth conditions of sentences, that is already a theory of meaning of the sentences of the language. Well, I don't think we'll go any further into the work of each of these individuals, Professor Searle. I think we ought to move on now to the second of the main lines of development that you mentioned. And that is the line of development that's concerned with the intentions of speech users. Now, the central notion here is the notion of the speech act, isn't it, which is indeed the title of your famous book. The idea is that sentences don't just kind of exist in limbo. They don't exist all by themselves, autonomously in the universe. They are generated by human beings. And they're always generated in actual situations. And they're always generated for a purpose, in order to do something. And the idea is, isn't it, that you can only understand meaning if you understand the intentions of the language user. What is he doing when he utters something? Would you take-- Yes, well, let me go on with that. In the tradition that we're now talking about, it isn't that there is a rejection of the question, what is the relation between language and the world. Rather, that question is put in a larger context. The question now becomes, well, what sort of behavior is linguistic behavior? And then the way that that is answered is in such a fashion as to try to explain how the speaker's intentions, how his rule-governed intentional behavior relates language to the world. So the question, how does language relate to reality, which I think is one of the fundamental questions-- perhaps the fundamental question in the philosophy of language-- is assimilated to what I think is the larger question. And that is, what is it about human beings that enabled them to, as you said earlier, make these noises that have such remarkable consequences-- among them is the consequence-- that they do relate to reality? Look, for me in this tradition, the fundamental question is how is it that we get from the noises that come out of my mouth to all these semantic properties that we attribute to them? After all, from a physical point of view, the noises that come out of my mouth are fairly trivial stuff. I mean, my jaw flaps open and I make this racket. And out it comes. And in linguistics textbooks, there's all this ridiculous stuff in my throat and mouth that enables me to do that. But physically, it's all rather trivial. And yet the most remarkable things occur. We say that Chap made a statement or asked a question or gave a command or an order, explanation, that what he said was true or false or interesting or boring or uninteresting. We attribute all these remarkable properties to it. And one set of those properties are those that related to the world. Now, the basic idea behind this second approach is that the way that language relates to the world is a matter of how people do that relating. And the basic term of that, at least in the tradition as I see it, is, as you said, the notion of a speech act. When people do communicate with each other, whether in words or in writing, they perform a series of acts that we have names for such as making statements, asking questions, giving orders, commands, apologies. Austin, incidentally, claimed that he could get a list of about 1,000 such verbs and verb phrases in English. Now, that is the alternative tradition. And I should say Wittgenstein's enormously important role in developing that-- the later Wittgenstein-- but it would be misleading if I said that he would agree with everything that I have said. And I think there's a basic point of disagreement. Wittgenstein, though he was really the person who gave this direction to the philosophy of language, the idea of looking at language as a form of human behavior and language as a form of life, nonetheless, he resisted making general theories of language. He thought any kind of general theorizing was almost about bound to lead to distortion and falsehood when we were doing philosophy. So though I regard myself as, at least in part, inspired by the work of Wittgenstein, I think he would reject the theoretical bent that I personally try to pursue and that Austin, I think, was pursuing. I was going to say, the other really big figure in this tradition, apart from Wittgenstein, the later Wittgenstein, is JL Austin-- now alas dead, he died rather young-- an Oxford philosopher. And, indeed, you were a pupil of-- Yes, I was, indeed. --of Austin, weren't you? Can you say just a lit-- he invented the term "speech act." He didn't quite invent the term. It did exist in certain structural linguists such as Bloomfield in the 1930s. But in its modern meaning, it is Austin's invention. And he arrived at it by quite an interesting route. Before Austin, the primary concern of philosophers of language had been with those utterances that are true or false. And indeed, as I was saying earlier, verification loomed large. And there were such questions as whether or not propositions that weren't verifiable could even be said to be meaningful, the logical positivists arguing that they couldn't. Now, Austin made an interesting observation. He observed that there are lots of utterances that don't set out to be true or false, that-- I mean, he gave the following example. He said, in a wedding ceremony and when the preacher says, do you take this woman to be your lawfully wedded wife, and the chap who says I do, according to Austin, is not describing a marriage ceremony. He's indulging in one. That is, his utterance isn't meant to be a description true or false of anything. He's performing an action. And Austin then observed a whole class of these utterances. When I say, I promise or I bet or I apologize or thanks or I congratulate you, these he called performatives. And he then made a distinction between these cases where saying something is doing something, where uttering these phrases, these ritual phrases is doing something. And he contrasted these so-called performatives with what he called constatives, those utterances that did set out to be true or false. But then the theory underwent an interesting sea change. He discovered that he couldn't make the distinction between performative really quite precise. The constative class was supposed to be sayings, and the performative class was supposed to be doings. But what he discovered is that, of course, that saying is a kind of doing as well. And that then led to what he called the general theory of speech acts, where all of our utterances are seen as speech acts. And in my own work, I have come to the conclusion that the basic unit of meaning, if I may so speak, is the speech act, that what we are looking for when we ask such things as what did he mean by that is precisely into those intentions with which his utterance was performed. That is to say, what kind of speech act was he performing-- statement, question, command, and so on? And then within the speech act, we'll need to distinguish between the kind of speech act is, whether or not it's a statement or a question or an order on the one hand and what its content is. I can both predict that you will leave the room and order you to leave the room or ask whether you will leave the room. Now, in some sense, I want to say all of those have the same content, though they have, what Austin called, different force. And he had a label for this. He called those illocutionary acts-- that is, the basic speech acts where we are saying something and saying it as a statement or question or a command-- as contrasted with those of our utterances that we can describe in terms of the effect they produce on people. Whether or not I convince you or amuse you or bore you or annoy you, those he called perlocutionary acts. Now, I think that bit of his taxonomy enables us to see that our quarry here, the target of our investigation is the illocutionary act, that large class that includes making statements, asking questions, giving commands, apologies, thanks, congratulations, and so on. And there it seems to me, if we investigate those-- and here, Austin unfortunately didn't live long enough really to do this investigation. But I have been working on it. And other people have tried to work on it. And there the crucial question is what is the structure of the illocutionary act. And that's the form-- and I think this is a derivative from Austin-- that is the form in which the question I was asking earlier has really come to take shape. And that is, if we ask what I said was the question, how do we get from the physics to the semantics, that then is translated into the question, how do we get from the utterance to the illocutionary act? So I think you can see a line of development there from Austin. But again, I want to emphasize that Wittgenstein wasn't like that. He did inspire much of this. But he would have thought that to do it in this theoretical way was almost invariably, almost bound to distort the immense complexity and subtlety of language. Now, you yourself have, as it were, taken up this work of Austin's. And you're developing it further. It's already several years since your book Speech Acts was produced. What are you working on now? Well, really I'm trying to carry this investigation into the next stage. If we really take seriously the idea that speaking a language is engaging in a form of behavior, then we're led to ask, well, in what sense of behavior exactly? And what is it about action that seems so crucial here? And this ties in with what, to me, are the two central questions in contemporary philosophy. And I think, in a way, they come together. The two questions are, how does language relate to reality, which all philosophers of language are concerned with the one way or another. And the second is, what is the nature of human action? What is it to perform an action? What is it to explain an action? Why is that the methods of science have not given us the kind of results in the study of human behavior that they've been able to give us elsewhere. Or to put that part more pointedly, why have so much of the social sciences seemed to be a bore and unproductive? Now, the way those two questions come together, or two families of questions come together, I want to say is in the notion of what philosophers call intentionality. Now, intentionality was a term introduced by Brentano. And it is, itself, a medieval term. And, at least the way I use it, the feature that certain mental states have of being directed at objects and states of affairs in the world is what I call their-- and what the following this tradition I call-- their intentionality. If we think of our beliefs and fears and hopes and desires, they're all, in this sense, intentional. If you believe, you must believe that such and such is the case. Or if you fear, you must fear something. Whereas for pains and tickles and itches, they aren't in that way directed. They are, so to speak, independent. They're not directed at objects and states of affairs in the world. Now, the way that this notion of intentionality ties in with the philosophy of language is this. The question that we've been posing-- and in philosophy, the way you pose the question is half the battle. If you can get your question raised exactly right, you're well on the way to a solution. The way I want to now repose that question is this. Given that our mental states are, so to speak, intrinsically intentional, they can't help but be directed at objects and states of affairs in the world, the question is, how does the mind impose intentionality on objects that are not intrinsically intentional, because the noises that come out of my mouth, as I was saying earlier, they're just noises. The marks that I make on paper, the pictures that hang on the wall of a museum are after all, again, just physical objects, bits of canvas with paint slashed on them or painted on them. And now we want to ask, how is it that these fairly trivial, middle-sized, physical phenomena acquire this remarkable capacity to represent the world and represent it in these different illocutionary modes, to be statements or questions or commands or pictures of Bryan Magee or of the Battle of Hastings? And that, I think, is the point at which the theory of language and the theory of action come together in this problem of intentionality. So you get a kind of double prong with the theory of speech acts. On the one hand, by seeing language as action, by seeing speaking as a form of human behavior, I think you get a deeper insight into language. You see how-- and to use a Wittgensteinian metaphor-- it meshes with the rest of our behavior. But now, by taking this representative feature, this intentionality of language back into your theory of action, you also see how actions themselves have a kind of intentionality, in the sense in which language is meaningful, it isn't such a move to say that actions can also be meaningful, that our intentions are a kind of representation of what we're going to do. Now, let me say having said that, that I'm not going back to argue for the ghost in the machine or saying that there are all these mysterious mental events occurring in this queer mental medium. I'm not going back to Descartes. I think it's a big mistake to suppose that the logical features of intentionality-- that is, how it is that the mind can represent the world, either in our mental states, beliefs, hopes, fears, and so on, or perceptions or in our representations of a public kind, in language-- it's a big mistake to suppose that those questions have to be the same as Descartes' questions, namely, well, what's going on in my mind? Is there some queer mental event occurring in my soul when I speak? So I want to separate the Cartesian questions, the questions about the nature of consciousness, from what, to me, is the basic question about intentionality, namely how do mental states represent? And how do they have this remarkable capacity to make objects represent? I mean, look at it this way. How can mere things represent? How can a mere object or noise stand for something in the world? So my current research, which is really going a step back from speech acts and into more basic primitive questions, speech acts asked the question, how does language represent the world? Now I'm concerned with the question, how does anything represent anything? And that, I think, is the question about intentionality. We've left one loose end in this discussion, Professor Searle, which I want to take up and tie up before we bring the program to an end. When you were earlier on sketching out the whole state of the subject, you mentioned linguistics and, in particularly, the work of Chomsky as being an important feature in the landscape. I think I must ask you before we do finally conclude to say just a little bit briefly about him. Yes. Well, of course, Chomsky, I think it's no exaggeration to say, produced a revolution in linguistics. What he did was take syntax as central to language. Now, that wasn't just the revolution. That had been done before him. But he took it in a particular way. He asked the question, how can we get a finite set of rules that will generate all and only the sentences of a language? And then he showed that these rules had to have certain very special logical features. But the impact that this has had on philosophy is quite interesting. And it's in different realms that it's had. One obvious thing is that it's given us new syntactical tools to do studies of language. I mean, in my own case for example, I use some of Chomsky's apparatus to try to show how different speech acts are realized in different syntactical forms in English. And I think one could do similar studies for other languages. But more importantly I think in Chomsky, he was led to the following conclusion. The syntax that he came up with was extremely abstract and complicated. And that raised the question, how can little kids learn that? I mean, that you can't teach a small child axiomatic set theory. Chomsky showed that English is much more complicated than axiomatic set theory. How is it that little kids can learn that? And his answer was quite interesting. What he said was, in a sense they already know it. It's a mistake to suppose that the mind is a blank tablet. What happens is that the form of all natural human languages is programmed into the child's mind at birth. I mean, in his strongest moments, Chomsky says that the child has a perfect knowledge of universal grammar at birth. And then his exposure to language just triggers this antecedent knowledge. And it's realized in the different natural human languages. Now, there used to be a traditional objection to this idea of a universal grammar. People would say, but languages are so different. English is so different from Chinese. Chomsky's answer to that was that though they're different on the surface, they have a common, underlying or deep structure. And it's that which is programmed into the child's mind. Now, that seems to me Chomsky's positive contribution. And I think it really is remarkable. But there are, I think, certain limitations. And those limitations have to do with the present disarray in linguistics. Chomsky sees man as, essentially, a syntactical animal. He never asked such questions as, well, what are these syntactical forms used for? And his notion of syntax is that this theory of the syntax of language must be stated in purely syntactical terms. That is, we're not allowed to say what these forms mean or how people are supposed to use them. And Chomsky's actually denied what seems to me to be true, namely that the purpose of language is communication. He doesn't think that that's the case. I mean, he thinks that-- He thinks it's expression. Well, that's right. And that language, the essence of language is syntax and that we have the syntax programmed into us, that we are, as I said, syntactical animals. Now, I think that leads to a certain limitation in his research. I think that the most interesting questions about syntax have to do with how form and function interact. And I want to ask the question, what are these syntactical forms for? Language, for me, is to talk with and to write with. So I want to say that the study of the syntax will always be incomplete, unless we get a study of linguistic use. Now, it's an effectual question. I mean, the research in the end and the long haul, it might show that he was right and I am wrong. But my gut feel is that we will not get an understanding of syntax of language and how language evolved without a conception of what human beings use language to do. And that's back to speech acts. Well, Professor Searle, you've given us an excellent survey, I think, of what the present situation is in the philosophy of language and also how it developed out of the past. Would you-- and I put this to you as my very last question-- would you conclude this discussion by hazarding some informed guesses about-- Well, I'll try. --how it's going to develop in the immediate future. Yes, I'll try. Left my crystal ball in Berkeley. But I'll see what I can do without it. First of all, I think linguistics is now such a booming subject, that that's bound to continue, partly because it's so well-funded. And I think linguists and philosophers are going to find each other useful. I mean, we're interacting more than we did in the past. I find myself at linguistics conferences and inviting linguists to come and speak in philosophy conferences. So I think, though the Chomskyan paradigm has broken down, there isn't the kind of unified development of linguistics as a science that there once seemed in the heyday of Chomsky's paradigm. Though the field is in kind of a mess, it seems to me that is going to continue, that the field will continue to develop. Linguistics will be a source of enormous usefulness for the philosopher of language, even though, of course, the direction of the interest that the linguist and the philosopher has are different. The linguist's interest is factual, empirical. He wants to know what are the facts about language. The philosopher really is more conceptual. He wants to know how is meaning and communication possible at all. His question, to use an old-fashioned jargon, is transcendental. It's not just empirical. So that's one thing that I think will continue. Now, another thing I think is really having a kind of a boom in England and in certain parts of the United States now is the work of Quine and Davidson and especially Davidson's idea that you can get a theory of meaning by way of a theory of truth. The thing that is so appealing about that is you get well-defined questions. I mean, you get questions that you can state using the apparatus of modern mathematical logic. And you get the sort of questions that Austin liked incidentally, questions where cooperative group effort could produce results. So I think that vein is, by no means, worked out. We're going to see a lot of interesting work done in the Davidsonian tradition. And finally, I want to say that the kind of stuff I'm interested in I think is going to continue to interest people. And I'm quite interested to see that on the European continent, where for so long there seemed really a kind of iron curtain between the way they did philosophy and the way we did philosophy-- I mean, French and German philosophy seem so different from Anglo-American philosophy. They're now getting more and more interested in precisely this aspect of language that we've been talking about. So I see at least these three strands of work going. Post-Chomsky-- and, of course, I'm including Chomsky himself in what I call post-Chomsky-- linguistics will continue to develop. I see more and more work going on in formal semantics of the Davidsonian kind. And I think a lot of useful work is going to be done there. And then I see these problems about language usage and intentionality. That seems to me a very rich field. More and more in the Searlean kind, as well. Thank you very much, Professor Searle. Thank you.
Info
Channel: mehranshargh
Views: 21,833
Rating: undefined out of 5
Keywords: John Searle (Author), Philosophy Of Language, Philosophy (Field Of Study), Searle, Witgenstein, Bryan Magee, Philosophy, language, John Searle, Berkeley, Bertrand Russel, Austin, Ludwig Wittgenstein (Academic), فارسی, ویتگنشتاین, فلسفه, جان سرل, تراکتاتوس, لودویگ ویتگنشتاین, رساله منطقی-فلسفی
Id: lGKaBUWrWwE
Channel Id: undefined
Length: 44min 24sec (2664 seconds)
Published: Sat Sep 05 2015
Related Videos
Note
Please note that this website is currently a work in progress! Lots of interesting data and statistics to come.