Is Consciousness Primary to Reality? (Documentary)

Video Statistics and Information

Video
Captions Word Cloud
Reddit Comments
Captions
The belief that consciousness or awareness is  fundamental to reality is an ancient philosophical   idea. It can be found in the writings of  many eastern and contemplative traditions,   such as buddhism and hinduism as well as in  western traditions such as in the philosophy   of ancient greece in platonic idealism. A  fundamentality of consciousness in reality   is a metaphysical position that has been defended  throughout history by scholars and sages alike.   And in various interesting cases, driven  not by ideological or religious convictions   but by philosophical deduction, introspection, and  ontological parsimony. Before we continue we need   to define consciousness. When we think of our own  consciousness many things may come to mind: Our   senses of sight and taste, smell and touch, our  rich palate of emotions, or our ability to think   about concepts and ideas. To philosophers however,  the word consciousness can be simply defined as   experience. It is commonly said that something is  conscious if there is something it is like to be   that thing, no matter how simple or sophisticated  that experience might be. It is in this way that   we will be using the word consciousness today.  In recent decades the idea that consciousness   is a fundamental element of reality has made an  unexpected return to Western academic thought,   enjoying a new credibility among respected  scientists and philosophers. It has been   the subject of both popular and academic books,  philosophical papers, and scientific monographs.   So why has this ancient and esoteric idea  returned to our modern thinking? Is it true   and what might it mean for us? This is the story  of how consciousness in Western academic thought   went from an insignificant illusion to a leading  candidate for the ultimate ground of existence.   To understand the recent resurgence of fundamental  views of consciousness we need to first go back to   the turn of the 20th century when a similar  flowering of such views was occurring in   western philosophy. Our story begins with one  of the leading academic figures of that time,   Bertrand Russell. A British polymath,  Russell's interests spanned philosophy,   science, mathematics, and literature. And  yet it was Russell's philosophical work   on the ancient mind-body problem, now  rediscovered by academics decades later,   that has now sparked a renaissance in considering  a deep place for consciousness in reality.   In his 1927 book, "The Analysis of Matter" Russell  focused on the enduring question of how mind   relates to matter. He adopted a stance on  matter similar to that taken by earlier   philosophers including Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz,  Immanuel Kant and later by Arthur Schopenhauer.   These thinkers had argued that, in spite of  the richly detailed description of the world   provided by physics, the physical account actually  offers no explanation of the nature of matter.   The core of the position is that physics tells  us not what matter is but only what it does.   Consider a particle. Physics tells us that  particles have the properties of mass,   charge, and spin. Yet these properties tell us  only about how a particle will relate to its   environment and nothing about the intrinsic nature  of the particle. --What it is in itself. This,   it turns out, is true of everything that  physical science tells us about the world.   In the popular understanding physical science  reveals the essential contents of reality, however   in actuality, science reveals only behaviors and  relationships, what we might call "the causal   structure of nature." And while it has proved  highly valuable in countless practical ways, the   intrinsic nature of reality --what our physical  equations are actually describing, remains an   unsolved mystery. As Russell writes, "We know  nothing about the intrinsic quality of physical   events." But does physics actually require  an intrinsic ground in order to be complete?   Perhaps structure and relationship are simply  all there is to reality. This view however falls   apart on closer inspection. As the philosopher  Hedda Hassel Mørch points out, "For there to be   a relation there must be two things being related.  Otherwise the relation is empty --a show that goes   on without performers or a castle constructed out  of thin air." She continues. "Physical structure   must be realized or implemented by some stuff or  substance that is itself not purely structural,   otherwise there would be no clear difference  between physical and mere mathematical structure,   or between the concrete universe and a mere  abstraction." This fact was not overlooked   by the late, great physicist Stephen Hawking who  famously pointed out that we have no idea what it   is that quote "breathes fire" into the equations  of physics and gives reality to the universe.   It would seem that there must be some essential  ground to which our physical equations actually   point. And without it, as Russell argued, our  account of reality will never be truly complete.   After presenting this view on  matter Russell went on to observe   that the elusive intrinsic nature of the  world is in a conspicuous way analogous to   the mysterious reality of consciousness. --We know  that it's there and yet it stubbornly resists all   attempts to capture it through objective or  behavioral processes. Russell argued that our   epistemological blind spot in physics: To get  at the nature of what things are in themselves,   is precisely the same reason that physical  approaches to consciousness seem doomed to fail.   --Intrinsic natures simply cannot be captured  through a purely physical approach. Russell did   not suggest that consciousness was the intrinsic  nature of reality but instead argued for a   position that has become known as "neutral monism"  in which reality has a single underlying nature   that is neither mental or physical but capable  of being expressed in these two different ways.   Much like interiors and exteriors, in Russell's  account the mental and the physical imply   and necessitate each other as reflections of  a single (hence monistic) underlying nature. In the 1920s Russell's arguments sparked interest  among several leading academics of the time,   most notably in Arthur Eddington. Like Russell,  Eddington was another titan of early 20th century   science. As a physicist and mathematician,  he was famous for demonstrating the validity   of Einstein's theory of general relativity, by  setting up an ingenious experiment that involved   the observation of stars as their light is  curved by the mass of the sun. Eddington was once   heralded as one of only three people in the world  to truly understand Einstein's general relativity,   and Einstein complemented his presentations on  the subject as the clearest in any language.   But aside from his scientific  contributions, Eddington   was also a celebrated philosopher of science  with a deep interest in the mind-body problem. In 1927, at the same time that Russell was  developing his neutral monism, Eddington was   invited to give a series of lectures at Edinburgh  University in Scotland for the prestigious   Gifford lectures -- a long-running annual event  considered by many to be among the highest honors   in a philosopher's professional career. It was  in these lectures and then in his later writings   that Eddington outlined a compelling solution  to the mind-body problem. It was a new synthesis   of an ancient philosophical position known as  panpsychism -- a name given to views throughout   history which place mind or consciousness  as a deep and ubiquitous feature of reality.   In these lectures Eddington argued that  there is only one plausible candidate   for the intrinsic nature of the physical world,  consciousness. Like Russell and others before him,   Eddington recognized that science gives  no description of the intrinsic nature   of the physical world. His primary contribution  however was to argue, convincingly to many,   that consciousness is precisely the required  candidate to fill this awkward gap in our   knowledge. Eddington put forward an argument for  panpsychism which is known today as "The Intrinsic   Nature Argument." This argument, now recently  rediscovered, has seen panpsychism return as   a respectable theory and a view that now enjoys  growing support from scientists and philosophers   alike. To explain the intrinsic nature argument  we first begin with an account of consciousness.   It is sometimes said that the existence  of consciousness is the one thing we know   for sure about reality. Perhaps the most famous  philosophical dictum of all time is that of René   Descartes, "I think, therefore I am." Whatever  we believe we may know about the outer universe,   there is only one feature of reality that is  utterly invulnerable to any and all doubt, our   consciousness. The world might be very different  to what our senses describe. Maybe we are a brain   in a vat, or living in some kind of simulation,  maybe we're just dreaming. And yet for all of   the ways we could be mistaken about reality,  we can be sure only that consciousness exists.   But other than its existence what else do  we know about consciousness?Eddington argued   that we know at least one thing concretely about  consciousness, --that it is an intrinsic nature.   In our unmediated access to it, consciousness is  a reality that we apprehend directly and without   inference. Consciousness exists uniquely to and  for itself. We might even go so far as to say   that consciousness is the only part of reality  that we truly understand, because only in our   consciousness do we have access to the intrinsic  nature of at least one small part of the universe.   But why then believe consciousness could be the  intrinsic nature of all reality? As it turns out   consciousness is both the only intrinsic nature  we know, or can conceive of. Only consciousness   exists to and for itself and it would seem that  this same property is required to ground the   physical world in reality. Previously Russell  had described our need for an account of the   intrinsic qualities of physical events. And yet it  would seem that qualities are the exclusive domain   of consciousness. Many philosophers, past  and present, have argued that a true account   of consciousness requires an expansion of our  physical picture of nature, and according to   the intrinsic nature argument, physics calls for  precisely this expansion in order to be complete.   For these reasons Eddington regarded nature's  grounding interiority as a perfect candidate for   the otherwise mysterious interiority of our minds.  Through this approach, mind and matter could be   unified, the interaction problems of dualism could  be averted, and the elegant economic ontology of   monism could be restored. As Eddington concluded,  (quote) "All through the physical world runs   that unknown content which must surely be  the stuff of our consciousness." (end quote)   ~An Idea Lost to History~ It is arguably due  to the turbulent events of the 20th century   that this earlier flowering of panpsychism  came to an end. In the wake of the first   world war a dramatic shift took place in analytic  philosophy. With the rise of Logical Positivism   academics argued that philosophy must now  dispense with metaphysical musings about   the nature of reality and earn its keep by  providing actionable contributions to science.   A consequence was that introspective and intuitive  knowledge was sidelined and not surprisingly, the   question of consciousness once again faded into  the background. During this time another similar   development was also underway in psychology  with the rise of Behaviorism. With hopes of   finally achieving the status of the hard sciences  B.F Skinner and other influential psychologists   directed the powerful objectivity of empiricism  to human behavior. With great ambition   psychologists now predicted that every datum  of the mind could be entirely understood by   reduction to environmental inputs and behavioral  outputs. For decades in the field of psychology,   even mentioning consciousness raised eyebrows. As  the field advanced however, it became increasingly   clear that denying mental states left out the  true essence of psychology; sensations, emotions,   feelings, and desires -- these were what made us  who we are as living beings with conscious minds.   While in some relative obscurity consciousness  continued to be discussed by philosophers,   it wasn't until the 1980s that consciousness  re-entered the broader academic discussion.   In the late 1950s the biologist Francis Crick  shot to fame for his role in discovering the   structure of DNA. With his place in the  pages of history secured, by the 1980s   Crick hoped to surpass even this discovery  by solving that other great mystery of life,   consciousness. Now, together with his colleague  neuroscientist Christof Koch, the two scientists   announced the beginning of a new scientific  program dedicated to finally demonstrating how   brains become conscious. Through their study  and the research it inspired a great many new   discoveries about cognition and neuroanatomy were  made. And yet in spite of their achievements,   how any quantitative description of the objective  processes of the brain could somehow lead to a   qualitative description of subjective experiences  remained a mystery. It gradually dawned on them   that any physical theory of consciousness is  forced to take no less than a leap of pure faith   from the objectively physical to the subjectively  mental -- what the philosopher Joseph Levine had   called "The Explanatory Gap." A century of  studying the brain had provided an impressive   and extremely useful science of correlations.  We learnt the specific brain states associated   with recognizing faces, solving problems,  feeling pleasure, pain, and excitement.   Yet the central question remained: Exactly how  do physical brain states produce mental ones?   In an important sense a century of neuroscience  had brought us no closer to understanding this   mystery. As the neuroscientist Antonio Damasio  reflected in an article for scientific american,   (quote) "One question towers above all others in  the life sciences: How does the set of processes   we call "mind" emerge from the activity  of the organ we call "brain." (end quote)   The effort to understand the nature  of consciousness seemed once again to   have encountered an impasse. And yet while  Crick and others collided with the ancient   mind-body problem, several philosophers were now  rediscovering strands of Russell and Eddington's   previous work. Among these philosophers were  Thomas Nagel, Galen Strawson, David Chalmers,   and William Seager. It seemed that between them,  Russell and Eddington had discovered an attractive   middle path for solving what was now being called,  "The Hard Problem of Consciousness." While their   approach had been convincing and influential  to several leading academics of the early 20th   century, as neither a form of materialism or  dualism, the nuance of the Russell Eddington   approach had been overlooked by much of the  mind-body debate of the time. Eventually it   had been obscured by a turbulent century of great  wars and revolutions in psychology and philosophy   which were hostile to the issue of consciousness  as a legitimate subject of inquiry. Now however,   in the latter part of the 20th century, hostility  towards metaphysics had largely subsided,   the limits of behaviorism had become obvious,  and the imposed restrictions on philosophy were   challenged by a new generation of philosophers.  It was now finally becoming clear that purely   behavioral or physical approaches could never  explain consciousness. A growing minority of first   philosophers and later neuroscientists began  to argue that consciousness could never   emerge from exclusively physical processes. That  consciousness, in some unrefined or proto-form,   must exist inherently within the natural  world -- a fundamental aspect of reality. Space, time, mass, and charge are all  considered to be fundamental features   of the world -- so called because they  cannot be defined by anything more basic.   Historically the advancement of science  has always led to the introduction   of new fundamentals and with them the expansion  of our scientific picture of the world. Now,   for a small but growing cadre of thinkers, we are  now at another such critical moment in history,   when a new fundamental must be recognized.  This time it is consciousness. Instead of   being a field-specific problem in neuroscience,  the mind-body problem looks increasingly to be   an issue that extends to our entire  understanding of the physical world.   As the philosopher Thomas Nagel wrote, (quote)  "The mind-body problem is not just a local problem   having to do with the relation between  mind, brain, and behavior in living animal   organisms -- it invades our understanding of  the entire cosmos and its history." (end quote) While panpsychism has now returned as a  respectable theory it is not without its   critics panpsychism, for many, is just too  weird to be true. And yet the weirdness of a   theory is not evidence against it. Indeed  a similar association once cast a shadow   over quantum physics, a field derided by Einstein  for its (quote) "Spooky actions at a distance."   Today, quantum physics is widely regarded as  the most powerful physical theory ever conceived   and its so-called spooky actions have been  widely demonstrated. Indeed Einstein's own   theory of special relativity tells us that  time slows down for objects as they accelerate.   --A scientifically demonstrable  fact that is at the same time   profoundly counterintuitive, with no basis  in our ordinary experience of reality.   The panpsychist view, that the interior quality of  our minds is continuous with the intrinsic inner   nature of the world, might sound very strange  and yet history teaches us to keep an open mind   to counter-intuitive theories and judge them  not by how they seem to us but by their elegance   and explanatory power. To the panpsychist it is  materialism that is the unintelligible position.   Through the Russell-Eddington approach we  can see that physics less reveals the nature   of reality than it is silent on the question.  Taking its physical description as the totality   of what exists begins to look like a classic  case of confusing the map with the territory,   and the resulting materialism less an account of  the nature of reality than the absence of one.   Now, to a growing number of  thinkers, only panpsychism   unifies the mental and physical facts of existence  and places them in necessity of each other. Alongside concerns about the strangeness of this  view, there are common misconceptions about what   panpsychism actually entails. If consciousness  is somehow fundamental, must we now believe that   rocks, tables, and chairs have conscious minds? In  fact, no serious thinker has defended such claims.   A complex mind requires a complex organization  with the specific capacity of aggregating a   fundamental aspect of consciousness. There  are now several scientific theories which   begin with a fundamental view of consciousness.  One such theory that has been widely discussed   is Integrated Information Theory or "IIT."  Developed by neuroscientist Giulio Tononi, IIT   is considered by many to be the leading scientific  theory of consciousness today. It is also,   conspicuously, a form of panpsychism. The theory  asserts that information, by its very nature,   has both a physical and mental pole, and that when  information becomes integrated inside a system,   an integrated consciousness emerges. In this  respect IIT is reminiscent of Russell's neutral   monism where the physical and mental are unified  aspects of a more primary reality of information. Tononi and his colleagues have developed methods  for gauging the integrated information present   in the brains of patients in their laboratory.  They appear to show that the presence of greater   amounts of integrated information does indeed  correlate with the presence of consciousness.   IIT also successfully predicts which centers  of the brain are associated with consciousness.   For example, why the cortex is so  central to consciousness in humans   even though it has far fewer neurons than the  cerebellum -- which can actually be removed with   only minor disruption to consciousness.  The reason, according to iit, is that   the neurons of this area are significantly  less integrated than those of the cortex.   And this is precisely what examining the  neural structure of the cerebellum reveals,   many more neurons than the cortex yet much less  integration between them. But Tononi's theory   does not confine consciousness to brains. IIT  predicts that integrated information and therefore   some amount of consciousness exists all around us  in all sorts of things. According to the theory,   every living cell, every electronic circuit,  even a proton consisting of just three elementary   particles, possesses something albeit but a  glimmer of consciousness. As Tononi has put   it, (quote) "Consciousness is a fundamental  property like mass or charge. Wherever there   is an entity with multiple states there is some  consciousness. You need a special structure to   get a lot of it but consciousness is everywhere,  --it is a fundamental property." (end quote) Tononi's theory does have its critics,  including among supporters of panpsychism.   For example, his theory takes no account of the  interconnected reality of the quantum world and   some increasingly argue that quantum effects,  such as entanglement between brain processes,   may yet be discovered to play an important role  in the unified nature of conscious minds. But   whether or not IIT is correct, it successfully  demonstrated to the scientific community   that testable forms of panpsychism can  be developed. It also revealed that such   a theory could have extremely important  medical applications, such as determining   if consciousness exists in unresponsive coma  patients, or the full effectivity of anesthetics. Philosophers at the Qualia Research Institute have  also thought deeply about the broader implications   of Tononi's theory. According to the philosopher  Michael Johnson, IIT predicts that consciousness   could exist far beyond the scale of humans  and animals and might in fact be present   in massive cosmological phenomena. Black  holes, for example, the surfaces of which are   predicted to contain massive amounts of integrated  information, could also have an enormous amount   of consciousness. Johnson also tentatively  speculated that for the same reason, the Big Bang   could itself have been a massive experience -- a  climax of cosmic symmetry echoing into infinity.   Neuroscientist Christof Koch, who  began his career as a materialist   working alongside Francis Crick, now takes  panpsychism very seriously. Describing his   radical shift in perspective he writes, (quote)  "The entire cosmos is suffused with sentience.   We are surrounded and immersed in consciousness.  It is in the air we breathe, the soil we tread on,   the bacteria that colonize our intestines, and  the brain that enables us to think." (end quote) ~Panpsychism and the Combination Problem~   Perhaps the most credible challenge to panpsychism  is what is known as "the combination problem."   This challenge to panpsychism was first raised  over a century ago by one of the founders of   modern psychology, William James. While James  himself was actually an advocate of panpsychism,   he pointed out that any panpsychist theory needs  to explain how more elemental conscious entities   combine to create more sophisticated minds  like ours. But how could a conscious entity   combine with another? As the philosopher Sam  Coleman has pointed out, it is the essence of a   conscious entity to have a specific viewpoint that  excludes other viewpoints. Under this definition   it's very difficult to conceive how multiple  simple conscious entities could combine to become   one. For its critics the combination problem  serves as a decisive refutation to panpsychism   perhaps equally insurmountable as the hard problem  of consciousness itself. And yet as defenders   of panpsychism have pointed out, we already have  highly convincing evidence that mental combination   does occur. The best example comes from  neuroscience. Many experiments have shown that   under specific circumstances, the two hemispheres  of the brain can become isolated from each other.   In such "split brain" cases a fascinating  observation is made, --each of the two   separate hemispheres appears to have their  own separate consciousness, capable of very   different personalities and desiring very  different things. Reconnect the hemispheres   and these two minds apparently merge to create  our normal awareness. Such split brain cases   reveal, at least in principle, that conscious  entities can combine to create larger minds.   Explaining exactly how this occurs would be a  task for a future science of consciousness, and   yet the fact that mental combination takes place  would appear to have already been demonstrated. ~Cosmic Mind~ Historically panpsychists  have attributed consciousness or mentality   to nature's fundamental entities. But what if  the most fundamental entity is not a particle   but the universe itself? Philip Goff has pointed  out that our historical tendency to view smaller   things as more fundamental might be a mere  assumption -- a tendency known as "Smallism."   Developing on a view known as "Priority  Monism" goth argues that we might equally   take the universe itself as the  primary ontological primitive.   After all, it seems quite natural to see the  universe itself as the most fundamental reality.   Goff offers a version of panpsychism he calls  "Cosmopsychism" in which the universe itself may   be the subject of a singular consciousness that  is refracted into individual minds like our own.   After all if panpsychist theories are  to take account of modern physics,   they must transcend the atomistic  thinking of previous centuries   and now accommodate the holistic fabric of reality  revealed in the quantum. Might the probabilistic   field that underpins classical reality now be  thought of as perturbations in consciousness?   That they are, as the philosopher Andrés  Gómez Emilsson has put it, "Fields of qualia."   In Bertrand Russell's early work he had  been highly critical of a position known   as "Ontological idealism," a philosophical view  in which the physical world consists entirely   of projections in consciousness.  And yet the species of panpsychism   developed from his later work in some ways  has a lot in common with ontological idealism.   In very general terms panpsychism argues that  the physical world contains a fundamental aspect   of consciousness. Ontological idealism on the  other hand views a fundamental consciousness as   containing the physical world. Through this  framing we can see that the two positions   are split on the issue of whether consciousness  contains the world, or vice versa. And yet the   real difference between these views may come  down to little more than a matter of perspective.   -That just like interiors and exteriors, mind  and matter imply and necessitate each other.   Indeed, it has often gone unrecognized that the  modern Russell-Eddington pansychism is itself   a form of idealism. The apparent  conflict between panpsychism and idealism   might be just a matter of from which side  we choose to begin. Ontological idealism   has often been criticized for failing to grant  sufficient reality to the physical world,   and for failing to account for the deep regularity  between our individual perceptions of nature --why   the world is so consistent and predictable.  The emerging panpsychism on the other hand,   preserves our highly useful and detailed physical  description of nature yet grounds it in reality.   It also finally offers an explanation for why  the physical world requires consciousness,   as the essential realizer of physics and  the basis upon which anything at all exists. Past academic revolutions, such as the  discovery that Earth orbits the Sun,   or that life evolved from a common ancestor,  re-situated our sense of place in the universe.   During these times millions of people paused  in their lives and looked around them,   and saw the world for the first time in a new way.  Many thinkers now believe that we are on the verge   of another historic shift in our perspective.  Yet this time the proposed shift is different.   It is an ontological revolution that could  not be more intimate to the core of our most   inner sense of self. For over 300 years in the  West, reasonable minded thinkers have adopted a   materialist view, in which a mature acceptance of  the received facts of science dispel all previous   notions of human specialness or our centrality on  the cosmic stage. That we live in an arbitrary and   unfeeling reality of inert physical laws, in  which we drift in an immeasurable cosmic void   separate and isolated from each other and  from true reality. The compromise of this view   and the strength it took to accept it were  seen as virtues in our promethean willingness   to seek and face reality. Now, once more, it  seems that reality is yet stranger and deeper   than previously imagined. But instead of further  decentralizing humanity and the conscious subject,   the emerging view offers a break in this  tradition. It recasts the physical world,   not as an inert matrix of matter, but as a  tapestry of qualities. And for the first time   since the dawn of the Copernican revolution  our significance in reality is promoted.   In the emerging view, consciousness -- the context  of all value, meaning, and significance is not an   arbitrary illusion of biological evolution  -- it is core to the ground of existence.   If consciousness is a fundamental property,  then in our most intimate and essential identity   as conscious beings, we are continuous  with the essential nature of reality.   More than ever we are at home in the universe,  as part of that tapestry of qualities   and the intrinsic experiencing  aspect of the universe itself.
Info
Channel: metaRising
Views: 307,299
Rating: undefined out of 5
Keywords:
Id: dYjnZCy_ZK4
Channel Id: undefined
Length: 38min 0sec (2280 seconds)
Published: Fri Jun 25 2021
Related Videos
Note
Please note that this website is currently a work in progress! Lots of interesting data and statistics to come.