Arthur Schopenhauer: Philosopher of Pessimism

Video Statistics and Information

Video
Captions Word Cloud
Reddit Comments

Description

Frederick Copleston and Bryan Magee discuss the work of the 19th century German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer. Schopenhauer is perhaps most famous for his extreme pessimism. Seeing the world as something horrific and bleak, he urged that we turn against it. As a follower of Immanuel Kant, he took space, time, and causality to be, not things-in-themselves, but categories of the mind through which we interpret and make sense of things. However, in contrast to Kant, Schopenhauer argued that reality must ultimately be one, which is essentially "Will". There are several remarkable things about him, including the fact that he was the only major Western philosopher to draw serious and interesting parallels between Western and Eastern thought, as well as being the first major philosopher to openly identify as an atheist. He had a significant influence on many great thinkers and artists, including Nietzsche, Freud, Wittgenstein, and Wagner. The arts were particularly important for Schopenhauer not only because he thought they give us a glimpse into the underlying reality, but because they help us to escape our individuality and thus the inherent suffering and meaningless absurdity of existence. (My Summary)

This interview is from a 1987 BBC program. Transcript/subtitles have been added.

👍︎︎ 2 👤︎︎ u/The_Ebb_and_Flow 📅︎︎ Sep 07 2018 🗫︎ replies
Captions
Arthur Schopenhauer was born in Danzig, now Gdańsk, in 1788. His family had been rich Hanseatic merchants for generations. And the upbringing he received was aimed not at an academic life, but at training him to step into an international business. However, he had no interest in the family firm, he insisted on going to university instead. And thereafter, he used his private means to finance a lifetime of independent study and writing. His doctorate thesis has become a minor classic, in spite of its title: On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. And he was still in his 20s during the four years when he composed his masterpiece, The World As Will and Representation, which was published in 1818, the year in which he was 30. From then until his death in 1860 at the age of 72, he published a great deal, but all of it was to extend or elaborate or enrich the philosophical system which he had constructed in his 20s, and from which he never departed. He produced a huge collection of essays called "Parerga and Paralipomena", and two short but pungent books on ethics called "The Basis of Morality" and "The Freedom of the Will". There was also a little book called, "On the Will in Nature", designed to show that his ideas were supported by discoveries in science. Most important of all, he published a revised edition of The World as Will & Representation which was more than twice the length of the original volume. There are several remarkable things about him. Although in direct succession to Kant's, his own work was securely in the mainstream of Western philosophy, he was genuinely knowledgeable about Hinduism and Buddhism, and is the only major Western philosopher to draw serious and interesting parallels between Western and Eastern thought. He was the first major Western philosopher to be openly and explicitly atheist. He placed the arts higher in the scheme of things and had more to say about them than any other important philosopher. And perhaps partly for that reason, his influence on creative artists of the front rank has exceeded that of any other philosopher of the modern era. He was himself among the supreme writers of German prose. Many of his sentences are so brilliantly aphoristic that they've been torn out of context by the hundred and published separately in little books of epigrams. Intellectually, this is a catastrophe, because it obscures the fact that Schopenhauer is first and foremost a system-builder, whose philosophy can be understood only as a whole. Of the books in print about him in English at the time of making this program, I have to confess to you that the longest & most recent is by me. But I can't very well interview myself, so I've invited the author of one of the others to come along and discuss Schopenhauer with me. My guest is, in any case, the most distinguished living historian of philosophy in the English language: Frederick Copleston, Emeritus Professor at the University of London. In addition to his extended treatment of Schopenhauer in his 9 volume History of Philosophy, he's written a separate book about him called: Arthur Schopenhauer, Philosopher of Pessimism. Well, Professor Copleston, I think the place we ought to start is by addressing ourselves to the question of what it was that Schopenhauer set out to do. Perhaps I should let you take that up. Well, Mr. Magee, I think that, like other original philosophers, a great many of them, Schopenhauer wanted to understand the world in which he found himself, the world in which he lived. Or one can say, he tried to form a coherent, unified interpretation of human experience; or to gain conceptual mastery over the world of phenomena, the plurality of phenomena. I think that is it. And to do that, Schopenhauer thought that it was necessary to identify the underlying reality. When asked why he thought that there was an underlying reality to identify, I suppose that the reason, one main reason, is that he started from the premises of Immanuel Kant. And that he thought that the way in which we see the world is a human perspective; that the human mind is pre-programmed to see the world in certain ways. We can't, for example, experience objects except as situated in space and time, as subject of spatial-temporal relations and as subject to the relation of causality. But it obviously doesn't follow that because things appear to one in a certain way that that is how they are apart from the way in which they appear, as they are in themselves. Kant certainly took it that the concept of a thing-in-itself as not as that which appears, can be considered in distinction from the appearance, was a sensible idea, and Schopenhauer took that over. I think this is such an important idea and we're going to come back to it in different ways, but it's worth going over again because it's difficult, I think, for people who are new to it to really get hold of it sometimes. Kant had argued that all possible experience can only come to us through our faculties, through our sensory & mental apparatus. And therefore, what we could experience depended not only on what there is "out there" to experience, but also on the nature of the faculties that we possess -- what our faculties could handle, what they do to what they handle, how they handle it and so on. So that all experience as such is subject-dependent. And he went on from that to argue that therefore we could see total reality as being divided into two. There are things as they are in-themselves independently of being experienced, and to such things we have no means of access. And then there's things as they appear to us, the world of appearances, the world as it comes to us through experience, and that's what we know; that's the world of common sense, the world of science, our total world. Now, Schopenhauer took this up from Kant and said now can we get any pointers, can we get any hints from a close analysis of this world of experience as to what it might be that underlies it, as to what it might be that lies behind it? That at least is part of the thought, isn't it? Yes, it is. I think it's important to remember that for Schopenhauer there can be only ONE underlying reality. Kant himself took it as a matter of common sense, I think, that if there's the table as it appears, then there must be the table as it is in-itself; and if the carpet as it appears, then there's the carpet in-itself; that there are a multitude of things-in-themselves. But of course, if we think away spatial & temporal relations and the causal relation, there's no means of distinguishing one thing from another. So that if the underlying reality transcends space and time and causality, and is quite other than the world of phenomena, then there can only be one. The plurality or multiplicity belongs to the world of phenomena but the underlying reality must be a "one". These ideas that we're dealing with are really so difficult that I think THAT is worth going over again as well. I think it'll help a lot of people. Schopenhauer argued that for one thing to be different from another thing, for anything to be different from anything else at all, this idea of differentiation only made sense with reference either to time or to space or to both. If two things are identical in time AND identical in space, then they're identical, period, they're the same thing. So, the notion of there being different things, in the plural, could only apply to this world of our experience, this world of space and time. Outside that world it could make no sense whatever to talk of anything being different from anything else. And therefore -- I'd just like to complete this thought. Therefore, whatever there is outside this world of our experience must be one and undifferentiated. And in taking that step from Kant, he thought Kant had been wrong in talking about things, in the plural, in-themselves, things as they are in themselves; that it must be one undifferentiated something that lies behind this world. Now, in saying that he took an enormous stride towards one of the central beliefs of Hinduism and Buddhism. Those religions also believe that behind this highly differentiated, plural, variegated world of phenomena, there is one single, undifferentiated something that manifests itself as this world. And one striking thing is that Schopenhauer didn't get the belief from Buddhism or Hinduism. He got it by arguing from premises that he derived from his predecessor Western philosophers. And then discovered that he'd reached a conclusion which was similar to that of the Buddhists and the Hindus. Yes. Well, I'd like to go back a moment to what you've been just saying about the only one underlying reality. I think that if one starts from the premises of Immanuel Kant -- I mean, I wouldn't myself, but if one does -- then Schopenhauer was right, because there's no means of distinguishing one thing-in-itself from another except as a matter of common sense. There's no formal way of distinguishing once you accept the Kantian premises that Schopenhauer did. Taking the argument to the next stage, so to speak, Schopenhauer thought that if we analyze this world of phenomena, we might get from it some clues as to what the underlying one -- which he called, following Kant, the "noumenon" or the "no-u-menon", it's a word from the Greek -- we might get some idea of what the noumenon is. And I think his great starting point was this. Kant had argued that all our knowledge of material objects must come to us and it can come to us only through our senses and there be, as it were, put together by our minds. Schopenhauer said well this is almost exactly right but there is one absolutely crucial exception to it which amazingly Kant seems to have overlooked. And that is that for every individual one of us, there is one unique physical object in the world, which we know in the way Kant says we know physical objects but we also know in a radically and entirely different way, namely directly from inside: and that is ourselves, our own bodies, our own persons. They are physical objects in the way that any other physical object is a physical object. And they can be seen and touched and heard and known in all the ways that other physical objects are known. But each one of us, in addition to that, has immediate non-sensory knowledge of this one physical object from inside, directly. And Schopenhauer thought that this knowledge of a physical object from inside might provide us with the key to the inner nature of things. That's what he thought. Personally, I think that if one starts with Kant's premises, then one must accept Kant's agnosticism. I don't see that there's any way of getting out of it. But certainly, you're quite right, of course, that that is what Schopenhauer thought, that there was an access through the body. The only difficulty is, it seems to me, that our idea, even our idea of an ultimate reality, belongs, on those premises, to the world of phenomena, and there's no way outside the circle and beyond there simply lies silence as Wittgenstein was to say in the Tractatus. However, it's quite perfectly true that Schopenhauer thought there was a hint given through our experience of our bodies, yes. I would want to defend Schopenhauer up to this point in the argument because he makes the point that the knowledge that we have of ourselves directly from inside is not knowledge of Kant's thing-in-itself, and there are two or three very important reasons why it's not. One is that the knowledge we have of ourselves from inside is still only a kind of superficial knowledge. Decades in advance of Freud, he argued very specifically and at length, that most of our own inner life and motivation and so on, is unknown to us; that our actions and our speech and our decisions are, for the most part, unconsciously motivated. So that in a very important sense, we don't even know our full inner selves. Another reason why he thought it wasn't knowledge of Kant's thing-in-itself is that it exists in the dimension of time, though it doesn't exist in the dimension of space. And time can be a characteristic only of this world of ours. And there was a third reason which I think is worth mentioning and it's this: Schopenhauer argued that all knowledge must be of a dual form: subject and object, knower and known, observer and observed. For there to be any knowledge at all of anything, you must have something that's grasped and something that's grasping it. And this differentiation can--for reasons that we were giving only a few minutes ago in a different context--differentiation can only exist within this phenomenal world, this world of experience, and therefore it's only in this world that there can be knowledge or there can be consciousness. Yes, that Schopenhauer anticipated Freud in remarkable ways is perfectly true and helps to show the importance of Schopenhauer in the history of thought, I think. But of course it's also true, I think, that all our ideas of the infraconscious, the idea that there is an infraconscious, that all belongs to the phenomenal world. And there we are. I mean, Kan't premises, Kant's conclusion. Now, we must start to say something about how he did point across the gulf, as it were, towards the noumenon. He thought that there was something about this inner experience of ours that gave us a clue as to what the ultimate nature of things outside this world is. Can you take up the story from there? Well, I'd say, for example, that my bodily movements for Schopenhauer would be expressions of desire or he used the word 'will'--perhaps unfortunately--but one might use 'force' or 'energy'. But, at any rate, if I move my arm, I will to move my arm. For Schopenhauer, as later for Wittgenstein, there's no entity called "the will" that is distinct from the movement of the arm and causes it, but the volition is the inside, as it were, of the movement and the physical movement is the outside; not trying to the deny that there is some inside. And if we consider that and, as you say, the unconscious motivation that lies behind a good deal of our actions, we can, at any rate, get the idea of a reality as a kind of infraconscious, below- conscious drive, that Schopenhauer called "Will", and that perhaps some better name can be given to, as 'force' or 'energy', something of that kind. But we have that hint as to the nature of the ultimate reality as an unconscious striving; a striving for existence, for life, for self-assertion.....you can describe it in various ways, of course. Yes, he thought that if we analyze this world of experience, the world of science if you like, the world of common sense -- which does consist for the most part of matter in motion, and most of it is matter in colossal amounts. I mean, galaxies & solar systems and so on, traveling through the cosmos at gigantic speeds approaching that of light. So the whole material universe consists of matter in motion to a degree that, so to speak, defies our imagination to really conceptualize it. And he argued--I mean, there were steps in the argument that we haven't time to go through-- but he argued, following on from Kant, that what is ultimate in all this must be energy. He argued that matter is, as it were, instantiated energy; that a physical object is a space filled with force; that ultimately all matter must be transmutable into energy. And it's very striking, I think, that that particular doctrine of his has been entirely borne out by 21st-century science. When the physicists in our century arrived at this conclusion they thought they were propounding something revolutionary and incredible, but in fact, Kant and Schopenhauer arrived at this conclusion over 100 years before them by pure, rational, reasoning of it out from ordinary experience. Yes. When one's talking about theoretical physics, one has to remember that so many physicists are sometimes loath to say that the terms such as 'energy' and so on, denote any reality of use within the framework of theoretical physics, but that it can't be taken that there's some kind of metaphysical reality called "energy" or so on. But I can quite see the point of substituting "energy" for Schopenhauer's "will". Well, you're attributing to me a step I don't quite take. I mean... Well, I'm glad. Yes. [LAUGHTER] No. I mean, what I wanted to say was this. Schopenhauer argues that what is ultimate in this world of phenomena, in his world of experience is energy. And at the scientific level, and speaking from the standpoint of our own day, he can be said to have been remarkably pre-voyant on that, to have been correct. Now, he says that the metaphysical, the underlying noumenon is whatever manifests itself as this energy throughout the cosmos, I mean, in the stars in the solar system, in animals, in trees, in falling stones, in ourselves, in everything. It's the unconscious energy that forms us in the womb that makes our organs work while we sleep and so on. And I understand him as saying that the nearest we come to getting any glimmering of what that is in experience is the experience we have inside ourselves of the energy, the go, the force, the will to exist, the will to survive; that somehow ultimate irreducible push or drive which is underlying to everything else. Yes. But then of course, Schopenhauer wasn't indifferent to the underlying reality, was he? I mean, he adopted quite definite attitudes, negative attitudes towards it, disvaluing it. And "energy" is such a neutral word. I mean, it's hard to say whether one approves of energy or disapproves of energy, likes energy or doesn't like energy; very difficult to say. Whereas Schopenhauer, as we're both very well aware, had very definite attitude towards the ultimate reality in its manifestations. But I think it would've been better if he'd used the word "energy" because he decided to give the name "Will" to this metaphysical reality and I think that's misled people ever since, because we can't help associating the idea of a personality with a will, or the idea of an aim with a will; when Schopenhauer himself reiterates at different points in his writings that he doesn't mean that, that in HIS sense of the word "will" everything has a will. A dead star or a stone has as much will as you or I. It is simply the metaphysical substratum, as it were, in everything. That it's not personal, not alive, not organic, has no aim, and so on. I think it's misled people and an impersonal word like 'energy' would've been very much better in my view. Well, I think you're quite right on that particular point. My own point that I was hinting at was that as Schopenhauer looked on the ultimate reality as perfectly revolting and was willing to speak of it on occasion even in moral terms as wicked--I mean, one wouldn't naturally be led to think of energy as revolting or as not revolting, at least I wouldn't. And certainly not as wicked! So, that's what I meant. He has this definite attitude towards the ultimate real-- and towards its manifestation of course: this world, empirical world. Now, perhaps we can, as it were, change our tack a little and confront that head-on. Up to this point in our discussion, we've been sketching what Schopenhauer's picture of reality was, what he thought the overall picture was. Now let's talk about his attitude towards it. He thought that the world was an appalling place, a terrible place. He thought it was full of injustice, disease, repression; that in the hospitals and prisons of the world were full of people going through the most appalling sufferings and tortures; that nature was red in tooth and claw; that in every hour of every day, thousands upon thousands of animals are tearing each other to pieces alive and devouring each other alive; and that the whole thing is a sort of appalling nightmare. It's an incredible vision, and it's expressed in prose of such dramatic power that no one who's ever read it is likely to forget it. But that was his view of the way things are. And therefore that the underlying metaphysical reality must be such as to express itself in these terms, and must therefore be something terrible, something nightmarish. That's why he is renowned, quite rightly, for being a pessimist. Yes. A pessimist above all philosophers; a bleak, black view of reality. And of course, he didn't leave it there, did he? I mean, he had suggested some ways out, the temporary way through aesthetic contemplation through art, through creation of art & through the appreciation of art, which stills desire and selfishness and longing and hostility and conflict for the time being, at any rate. Just as one can go into an art gallery and look at the pictures without desiring anything, but then, of course, one comes out and runs into a cafe or a pub, and need and desire reassert themselves. But it's a temporary way out. I think it was a mistake for Schopenhauer to bring in at that point the Platonic Ideas as the intermediate between the ultimate reality and the work of art because I don't see there's much place in his system. But he's quite right in making a distinction between the aesthetic attitude towards things and the attitude of trying to appropriate them and use them for one's own advantage. It's quite true there, there is a temporary way out. Yes, you're making the point that he thought that the aesthetic attitude was disinterested. Normally, if I see a plate of food I think in terms of eating it, this is something for my own sustenance or to satisfy my lusts or desires or greed or just simply hunger or whatever it might be. Whereas, if I see a Dutch painting of a plate of food, I don't see it in that light at all. I see it as an entirely sort of impersonal, disinterested way and then I'm conscious of its presence or absence of the aesthetic qualities such as beauty or lack of beauty it may be, but it's quite a different way of looking at things. One point that I think is worth drawing attention to in Schopenhauer's aesthetic is that he did think that the arts provided us with a special way of knowing things. And by that very token, he did not regard them as a means of expression. If I produce a work of art, what I'm doing primarily according to Schopenhauer isn't expressing my emotions or giving expression to my feelings, it's expressing insight or knowledge into something about the way things are. I think what can give meaning to that is in the idea that was going around when I was an undergraduate in the 20s, propagated largely by Clive Bell's significant form. One might put that instead of the Platonic Ideas, something like that. I think it's... As to the idea of truth in art, I think it's a very interesting subject and a difficult subject and I've never really made up my mind about it as to the truth in art. I think one must have -- though it's rather off the point -- an analogical view of truth in which truth according to the context can be understood in different ways as corresponds in one context but not, I think, in art. It wouldn't, it would be another kind of truth and that has to be examined. I think it's a perfectly respectable line of thought, certainly, and one well worth pursuing. I certainly [wasn't] making a critical remark about Schopenhauer's use of the Platonic Ideas. I didn't mean to say that I didn't think there was anything is in view of art, because I do, I think it is very well worth considering, certainly. And it's had an enormous appeal to many great artists. Oh, yes, certainly. Who obviously therefore thought that it corresponded to their conception of what it was they were doing. Undoubtedly, undoubtedly. I think we must move on now to a consideration of Schopenhauer's morals. What would you say was the place for morality or ethics in a world as painted by Schopenhauer? Well, as you know, Schopenhauer insists that as there's one ultimate reality, and each one of us is identical with that one ultimate reality, therefore, in some sense, we're all one, ultimately. And he uses that for advocating compassion, sympathy, Agape, love as distinct from erotic love, I mean, as distinct from Eros... I mean, that's very noble that he should uphold that idea of compassion and so on. It's difficult to see how each one of us is an embodiment of that horrible reality that there's much room for mutual love. Conflict would've been more like it, I should have thought. But at any rate, he certainly, undoubtedly values love against hatred and compassion rather than cruelty and so on. I certainly don't want to question those valuations of Schopenhauer, far from it. But ultimately of course, as we're all the one will and the will is something horrible, the ultimate ideal can only be turning against the ultimate reality. I'd like to keep these two notions separate for the moment. Before we move on to his idea of turning against reality, I'd like just to say a little more about his view of morals and ethics, because it was, in a sense, applied metaphysics in a rather unusual sense for a philosopher He had, as you say, this metaphysical view that we were all ultimately "one". And again, that is in common with some religions. And therefore, that in doing you an injury, I am in some significant ultimate sense injuring myself. And that my ultimate oneness with you is really the basis of morality, the basis of compassion, the basis of empathy. It's why I should behave towards you in morally approved ways and not behave towards you in aggressive ways. And you were quite right to say that there's an apparent conflict between regarding the metaphysical, the ultimate metaphysical reality as awful and evil and nightmarish in the way we were talking about a few moments ago, and regarding it in this context as the basis of compassion, empathy, and morality in general. I would like at this point to say that the famous fact-value distinction applies as much to Schopenhauer, in my opinion, as it does to anyone else. That is to say, that you can accept his view or a great deal of his view about how things are, about what reality is, without accepting his evaluation of it or taking up his stance towards it. And I say that with feeling because, in fact, I'm an example, I think, of this. I do regard very large parts of Schopenhauer's philosophy -- by no means all of it -- but large parts of it I regard as being valid and as having enormously rare and important and genuinely deep insights. And I think it casts great illumination. But I'm not a pessimist in Schopenhauer's sense at all. In other words, I accept his picture of the way things are, to an important degree, but I don't at all take up his view of it all as being a nightmare or whatever it may be. So I would go along with the ethics of Schopenhauer -- in fact, I think his ethics is very well-founded -- and wouldn't want to as it were, keep that part of his philosophy with which it's in conflict. As you know, a good many philosophers now question the fact-value distinction... I think it has an indispensable use myself, because one must distinguish, for example, between the way in which people behave and the way in which they ought or ought not to behave. The two propositions are different types, that's perfectly obvious. On the other hand, I don't think myself, that one can have any interpretation of the world that doesn't contain value judgments -- value judgments of importance, of significance and so on -- anymore than you can have a history that goes beyond mere chronology and that really tells a significant, coherent story. You can't have a history without value judgments. I don't believe in value-free history or value-free metaphysics. So although I'm willing to accept some distinction, I'd be very careful about applying it myself and simply saying, well, we can have this interpretation of the world on the one hand which is value-free & then the set of valuations on the other, because I don't think things work out in quite that way, you know. No, I didn't think they work out in quite that way either. I was merely making the point that you could have a lot of Schopenhauer and I was always careful not to say all but only a lot of Schopenhauer's view of the way things are, without sharing HIS value judgments. I would have other value judgments and I would entirely agree with you that you can't have a view with no value judgments. I think that's absolutely correct. But now, let us move on, as it were, to the final stage of Schopenhauer's philosophy, when he, taking his value judgments, seeing that reality in all or in most of its manifestations is an evil, a frightening, a nightmarish thing. The final step in his philosophy, which some have embraced and others have found impossible even to understand sometimes is he says we must reject this. Ultimately, we must reject reality, we must deny reality; the famous denial of the will. Can you perhaps try to explain a little more about what's involved in that concept? Well, I'd say that if you turn... Well of course, he entirely approved of the asceticism, self-mortification, and so on, that one can find in several of the world religions, advocated at any rate, and practiced in the past. And he thought that constituted a stage on the way towards a kind of final rejection of the will -- I don't quite know what form that would take -- but it would take, I suppose, the form of entry into a Buddhist Nirvana interpreted as nothingness. Well Schopenhauer would say that it may possibly have qualities of which we know nothing and can know nothing. But as far as we're concerned, to turn against the ultimate reality as we form a conception of it is to turn to nothingness, to nonexistence. That's why I would say that in spite of all the real resemblances between, say, Christianity, Buddhism, and Schopenhauer's philosophy, there is a fundamental difference between his attitude and, say, that of the Christian, the Muslim, and the Orthodox Jew, because they believe in God, they certainly wouldn't regard it as desirable that one should chuck God overboard or deny the ultimate reality in that sense. So there, it seems to me, there is a gulf. But more important -- because people might sweep that aside and say, well, I'm neither a Christian nor a Muslim nor a Jew -- but even in terms of Schopenhauer's own philosophy, I don't see how it's possible to turn against the will because it's the will that has to deny itself; I AM the will. And if this ultimate reality is going to deny -- how's it gonna deny itself, in and through me? It can't produce nothingness exactly. I don't see how... The more I think about it, the more difficult I find to envisage that ultimate rejection of the will as taking place when the will itself has got to do it. Before we finish this discussion, I'd like us to say a word or two about Schopenhauer's influence on other people. He's had enormous influence on creative artists and I referred to that. I didn't name any, but one might name Wagner, an enormous influence, Turgenev, an enormous influence; in fact, lots of major novelists of the last 100 years: Conrad, Thomas Hardy, Proust, Thomas Mann, etc. But perhaps in a discussion which is about philosophy, what we ought to concentrate on is not that so much as his influence on other major thinkers. And I think three stand out in importance: Nietzsche, Freud, and Wittgenstein, in chronological order, as having been very obviously & strikingly influenced by Schopenhauer between his day and ours. Could you perhaps say something about his influence on Nietzsche? As you know, Nietzsche regarded Schopenhauer as an educator, and his early work with Schopenhauer as educator indicates, I think, that he thought of Schopenhauer as a man who wasn't content with the superficial view of things, but looked underneath and wasn't afraid to look the world and history in the face. And didn't try & gloss over everything as Leibniz did with talk about the best of all possible worlds, but really looked the world in the face and was therefore a man of mental integrity. He also entirely agreed with Schopenhauer's subordination of intellect to will, in its first instance, the servant of the will. And also I think he regarded Schopenhauer as a man of great independence of character who didn't allow his views to be dictated by society, or by his predecessors, for the matter of that, or other philosophers, but thought them out for himself. But he came, of course, to criticize, as you know, Schopenhauer, in the course of time, for his turning away from life. And although it's been said of Nietzsche by Professor Crane Brinton that the great yeasayer spent most of his life saying no, Nietzsche did officially uphold the affirming of the world as it is. And, in a way, I sympathize with Nietzsche because I think if the world is as Schopenhauer said it is, then the best thing is to try and alter it for the better. I don't say that Nietzsche -- well, he thought... I mean, I wouldn't agree with Nietzsche's idea of what would be for the better, but there I do agree with Nietzsche. But on the other hand, he never ceased to admire Schopenhauer and revere him as a man who'd set him on the right path, away from convention, a great questioner. Well, I think we must now turn finally to the latest of the great thinkers who was directly influenced by Schopenhauer: namely Wittgenstein. Perhaps you'd like to conclude this discussion by sayin' a little about Schopenhauer's influence on Wittgenstein. Thank you. Yes well that's of course quite clear, isn't it? I mean, from the material preparatory to the Tractatus in the notebooks & in the other manuscripts, the debt of Wittgenstein to Schopenhauer is made quite clear. And in the Tractatus itself, this idea to which you referred earlier in our conversation of the correlation between the subject and my world, that is strong in Wittgenstein. There's I and my world. And that the I, the epistemological subject, is, as it were, the boundary of my world, it's not an object in my world. Because if I try to think of myself, then it's the I that's trying to think of myself. But it's on the borderline, as it were, of the world. That comes straight out of Schopenhauer. Then the famous saying in the Tractatus that if all of the problems of science were answered, the problems of life wouldn't have been touched. That also really comes from Schopenhauer, I think. And it's also noteworthy that in the Tractatus, Wittgenstein makes a distinction between the will as the bearer of ethics, of which he says nothing can really be said, -- that's the meta-phenomenal will -- and the will as a phenomenon, which forms part of the subject matter of psychology rather than of philosophy, for the author of the Tractatus. And, therefore, there is that distinction between the metaphysical will, I think, metaphenomenal will and the phenomenal will, which also can be traced, I think, to Schopenhauer. I should say that Wittgenstein, in the course of time, became less and less Schopenhauerian, in the sense that he became less and less addicted to forming a system, whereas as you said much earlier, Schopenhauer was certainly a system builder. There is a kind of embryo system in the Tractatus, but there's very little, as we all know, in the later writings of Wittgenstein. But still, he undoubtedly was strongly influenced by Schopenhauer. And in fact, he's about the only major philosopher of the past, that was in no sense contemporary, that Wittgenstein really read and studied and digested at all. So, it shows that the influence of Schopenhauer by no means ended with the 19th century, but as you said earlier, has lived on into the 20th century, and is embodied in one of the most famous philosophers of our century and time. Thank you very much Professor Copleston.
Info
Channel: Philosophy Overdose
Views: 161,557
Rating: 4.9293566 out of 5
Keywords: Philosophy, Schopenhauer, Arthur Schopenhauer, Metaphysics, Epistemology, History of Philosophy, Kant, Idealism, Free Will, Pessimism, Nihilism, Existentialism, Nietzsche, Monism, World as Will and Representation, Transcendental Idealism, Theory of Knowledge, Immanuel Kant, Buddhism, The Will, Transcendental, Determinism, Principle of Sufficient Reason, Natalism, Absurdism, Psychology, Thing-In-Itself, Noumenon, Noumenal, Experience, Critical Philosophy, Ethics, Fact-Value, Antinatalism
Id: GHMD05OcJTQ
Channel Id: undefined
Length: 42min 6sec (2526 seconds)
Published: Sat Feb 20 2016
Related Videos
Note
Please note that this website is currently a work in progress! Lots of interesting data and statistics to come.