Aristotle's Wheel Paradox - To Infinity and Beyond

Video Statistics and Information

Video
Captions Word Cloud
Reddit Comments

i don't like the way she introduces the notion of uncountability.

rationals are countable, but similarly, you couldn't state the smallest positive rational #

👍︎︎ 3 👤︎︎ u/Regular_Pudding8150 📅︎︎ Jul 21 2020 🗫︎ replies
Captions
- This episode was made possible by Brilliant. Hey there, welcome to up "Up and Atom" I'm Jade and I want you to imagine that you're an ancient mathematician, trying to figure out the circumference, the outer edge of this wheel. Now you can't exactly use a ruler and measuring tapes don't exist yet. So, what can you do? Well, one way would be to roll it one full rotation and measure the distance it traveled. You're feeling extra curious today and you want to try the same thing with the differently sized wheel but then you notice something interesting. There is actually a smaller circle inside the larger wheel which seems to have traveled the same amount. So, does that mean it has the same circumference? Well, that doesn't seem right. Intuition tells you that the smallest circle should have a smaller conference and therefore should have traveled a shorter distance. So, what's going on? This is a paradox known as Aristotle's Wheel and it originated in an ancient Greek text called "Mechanica". It tortured mathematicians and philosophers for centuries. And in this video, we're going to solve it. One attempt to figure out what was happening was made by a French mathematician named Gilles de Roberval. Now I'm way too Aussie to say that without probably offending some French people. So, I'm gonna get my French husband to say it. - Gilles de Roberval. - And he focused on the path traced out by the point on the circumference of a rolling circle. (light-hearted music) This distinctive shape is called a cycloid. He then wanted to see what happened when we traced out the path made by the inner circle too. The line traced out by the smallest circle is kind of stretched out. In fact, the smaller the inner circle is the more stretched out the path seems to get. So, what does this mean? While you think about that, let's take a look at another attempt to solve the problem. This puzzle also captivated the mind of the great astronomer Galileo and to figure out what was happening, he decided to look at a wheel made of hexagons. Just like with the circles, the wheel has a large outer hexagon and a small inner hexagon. When you roll the large hexagon, it travels a distance equal to the sum of the length of its sides. Just like a circle rolls out the length of its circumference. Now let's take a closer look at what the inner hexagon is doing. We can clearly see it lifting off the path, even though it travels the same distance as the bigger wheel, it's sides aren't touching the entire time. I wanted to make this extra clear for you guys, so we're going to mark out the track made by the wheels. (light-hearted music) There, a nice clean skip. Galileo then imagined what would happen if you repeated the experiment with a shape with even more sides, like an octagon. Here we see that the skips are shorter and more frequent. He then imagined a circle as a polygon with an infinite number of sides. He concluded that the inner circle must be making an infinite number of skips. While Galileo wasn't exactly right, it does get us closer to the modern day solution. When we put Galileo and Roberval's conclusions together we get only one possible answer. The inner circle must be slipping. Unlike the hexagon and the octagon the inner circle is not skipping as it never leaves the surface. So, the only possibility is that it's getting dragged along with the outer circle. This seems like a pretty simple answer. So, why did it baffle some of the greatest minds of history? Well, first, this isn't how we generally think of slipping. Usually we think of it as something like this, where one point on the circle stays in contact with the path, but anytime the outer circle rotates, the inner circle rotates by the same amount. The outer circle never pauses to let the inner circle slide along to catch up. It's all happening in the same continuous rolling motion. Another way to say this is that each point of contact between the circles and the path is unique. But how do two circles of different sizes both make unique points of contact with the surface through the entire rotation? Do the two circles have an equal number of points? As one scholar put it, "This is where the problem begins, not where it ends." Let's talk about what it really means for one thing to be equal to another. If I have this many objects, how do I know if I have an equal number of each? Well, one way is to pair the objects together and see if there are any leftover. If there aren't any leftover, I have an equal number of each. This is called a one-to-one correspondence. And it was thought that if two sets of objects have a one-to-one correspondence, they're equal. Seems legit. Now let's try the thing with circles. To simplify things, let's roll them out into their circumferences. A circle is just a rolled up line, after all. Now we have what would appear to be two differently sized lines. Let's see what happens when we try to make a one-to-one correspondence between them to make sure that we really are choosing unique points on the line. We have to make a triangle. Draw a line from the tip of the triangle, through the shorter and longer line. No matter what angle the line is drawn it will always intersect each line at a unique point. If you don't believe me try finding a unique point on either line and drawing back up to the tip of the triangle. A unique point on one line will always correspond to a unique point on the other. So, then there does exist a one-to-one correspondence between two lines of different length. This complicates our idea of what it means for two things to be equal. In fact, if we take a segment of the line we can still draw a one-to-one correspondence between any point on the line and any segment of the line. So, any segment of a line has a one-to-one correspondence with the line itself. So, does this mean that all lines are equal? That even a segment of a line is the same size as the line itself? Well, actually it's just the opposite. All of this leads to the very strange conclusion that a one-to-one correspondence does not always mean that two things are equal. The implications of this run very deep when we consider that numbers can be represented on a line. But wait, let's take a step back. What about these guys? We showed that a one-to-one correspondence between them meant they were equal, right? So, why does it work for these guys and not these guys? Can you spot the difference? Well, these objects are discreet, you can split them up into neat individual packages while these objects are continuous, uninterrupted, you can't split them up. Let's see how this fares when we talk about a very specific type of object, numbers. Take all positive whole numbers. Whole numbers are discrete because there exists spaces between them. They're better represented as dots rather than a line. There are an infinity of them because no matter how high you count, you can always add one more. Now, take all the negative whole numbers, same deal. No matter how low you count, you can always go lower. Every positive whole number can be paired with a negative whole number in a one-to-one correspondence. So, the number of positive whole numbers is equal to the number of negative whole numbers. The sizes of their infinity are equal. This might seem like a weird thing to say, but just hold on. We can also count them even though we would never stop counting, we can at least start counting. Now, let's start adding numbers. Let's add the fractions, the decimals, the irrational numbers, the transcendentals. In fact, let's add every number until there are no more gaps. This makes up what is called the real number line. Unlike the whole numbers which are discreet, the real numbers lie on one continuous line from negative infinity to positive infinity. If you point to any way on the real number line, there will always be a number there. Now let's do something. Let's take a segment of the real number line, zero to one and then let's take the segment one to 1 million. Here's the thing, just like with our two differently sized lines from before we can always find a one-to-one correspondence between any point from zero to one and any point from one to 1 million. This leads to the conclusion that there are equal amount of numbers between zero to one as there are one to 1 million. In fact, there are an equal amount of numbers from zero to one as zero to infinity. To really hit this home, let's say what happens if we try to count the numbers between zero and one. What is the first number after zero? Well, let's just ball park it and say it's 0.01 but then we can just add another zero to make 0.001 or 0.0000000000001. In fact, the question, "What is the next number after zero?" is impossible to answer because for any number we choose there will always be a number that is closer to zero. So, we can't even count the numbers between zero and one let alone zero and infinity. The amount of numbers that lie between zero and one and zero and infinity are both uncountably infinite. This is very different to the infinity of the whole numbers, which we can count and list. So, here we have two different types of infinities, countably infinite, and uncountably infinite. The surprising result that there are different kinds of infinities was the work of Georg Cantor. I've made a video which goes more into this idea and gives you the proof of it if you're interested. The paradox of Aristotle's Wheel took over two millennia to solve. While the physical answer turned out to be pretty simple, it led to some very strange ideas about what it means for two things to be equal and the strange nature of infinity. It's a reminder of the mysteries that surround us in everyday life if you just take a closer look. If you're curious about the world around you, but are not sure where to start, one resource I use is Brilliant. So, Brilliant is a problem solving based website and app with a hands-on approach. It's math, science and computer science content help guide you to mastery by taking complex concepts and breaking them up into bite-sized understandable chunks. I find that it's a really good way to learn because it forces you to think hard by answering questions as you go. In fact, if you liked today's episode, you'll like their course on number theory. It goes into more detail about the nature of infinity and best of all you can work through it at your own pace. They have over 60 courses and are always adding more, including an entire one dedicated to infinity coming soon. I will definitely be checking that out as I'm sure there is still so much to learn. If you'd like to go ahead and sign up, the first 200 people to sign up with this link will get a 20% discount off premium membership. Just go to brilliant.org/UpAndAtom. Great, thank you for watching and I'll see you next time. Bye. (upbeat music)
Info
Channel: Up and Atom
Views: 983,927
Rating: 4.8338366 out of 5
Keywords: family fun, math, math video, math for kids, physics, science, science video, paradox, education, up and atom, stem, steam, women in stem
Id: mrVg9GM5h7Q
Channel Id: undefined
Length: 13min 14sec (794 seconds)
Published: Thu Jun 11 2020
Related Videos
Note
Please note that this website is currently a work in progress! Lots of interesting data and statistics to come.