2020 Tanner Lecture on Human Values - Theorizing Racial Justice - Charles W. Mills

Video Statistics and Information

Video
Captions Word Cloud
Reddit Comments
Captions
- [Tad Schmaltz] Good afternoon, everyone. Thanks for joining us. I'm Tad Schmaltz. I'm chair of the philosophy department, and I'd like to welcome you to the 41st annual Tanner Lecture on Human Values at the University of Michigan. President Schlissel will introduce our speaker, Charles Mills, in just a moment, but first, I'd like to say just a few words about the Tanner Lecture and the people for whom they're named. The Tanner Lecture on Human Values, which is administered by the philosophy department, was permanently endowed by Grace Adams Tanner and Obert Clark Tanner in 1978. However, a lecture at Michigan the previous year by the political and legal philosopher Joel Feinberg inaugurated the series. In addition to Michigan, five other institutions were originally designated as permanent sponsors of the lectureship, so Clare Hall at the University of Cambridge, Brasenose College at the University of Oxford, Harvard University, Stanford University, and the University of Utah. Yale University and the University of California at Berkeley were added in 1987, and Princeton University was added in 1988. So we beat out University of California at Berkeley and Princeton. Over the years, the lecture has been delivered at other universities worldwide, and the lectures themselves are published in an annual volume. The Tanners had broad intellectual interests. Grace Tanner's interests inclined towards the sciences, especially biology and anthropology. Obert Tanner studied at the University of Utah in philosophy and law. After receiving his law degree, he studied and taught philosophy and religious studies at Harvard and Stanford and was professor of philosophy at the University of Utah for 27 years. He also was a successful businessman, having founded and that's rare for a philosopher, having founded, in 1927, the O.C. Tanner Company, which produces a range of jewelry that businesses use to reward individual achievement. The Tanners were generous philanthropists. They supported the Utah Symphony Orchestra, Ballet West, and the Utah Opera Company. They also built more than 40 public fountains and established philosophy libraries at 11 major colleges and universities, including our own splendid one here at Michigan in Angell Hall. Over the years, many distinguished intellectual figures have delivered the Tanner Lectures at Michigan, including Sir Karl Popper, Toni Morrison, Henry Louis Gates, Jr., and most relevantly for our lectures today, John Rawls. Here at Michigan, it is our practice to take the Tanner Lecture as the occasion for thorough consideration of its ideas. Each year, we have a program the morning following the lecture in which scholars from various disciplines offer perspectives on the lecture and join in a panel discussion. This year, the symposium will be held tomorrow morning, starting at 10 a.m., in the Rackham Amphitheater located on the fourth floor of this building. Our symposiasts this year are Samuel Freeman of the University of Pennsylvania, Michele Moody-Adams of Columbia University, and Nikhil Pal Singh of New York University. Now, to introduce this year's Tanner Lecture, I am pleased to present Mark Schlissel, the president of the University of Michigan. (audience applauding) - [Mark Schlissel] Thank you very much, Professor Schmaltz, for the introduction. Welcome, everybody. Thanks for coming today. A special shout out to our students who are in the audience today. It's really an honor to be here for the Tanner Lecture on Human Values and to learn from our special guest, Dr. Charles W. Mills. Today's Tanner lecture and tomorrow's symposium give our community a tremendous opportunity to deeply consider important issues that demand our full intellectual attention. The purpose of the lectures is to advance and reflect upon the scholarly and scientific learning related to human values. And in Dr. Mills, we have a pioneering scholar who's added new dimensions of thought to the examination of human values. In a review of Mills's sixth book, Black Rights, White Wrongs, a Critique of Racial Liberalism, Johns Hopkins professor Christopher Lebron writes that it represents the culmination of more than two decades of work on the philosophy of race and social justice. Lebron, in the piece published in The Nation, goes on to say that he likes to think of Mills as Socrates, roaming the philosophical streets, asking people why they think a society like ours, stained by a history of racial horrors, is not more ashamed of itself and why its leading minds do not make that shame a motivating force in the struggle for a more just society. While his body of work and influence befits such a lofty comparison, Dr. Mills came to the Socratic path through a combination of life experience and intellectual curiosity. After earning an undergraduate degree in physics, Dr. Mills switched to philosophy for his graduate studies. He has said that he was looking for a subject that could provide a big picture overview of what's going on. Combined with his formative experiences with the radicalization of the Anglo-Caribbean in the 1970s and the challenge to the postcolonial neocolonial social order, he would eventually rewrite that big picture. He took on a discipline that he found to be very white, and he points out that his work began for the most part before critical philosophy of race and widespread confrontations of colonialism. He is now a leading voice in challenging the dominant narratives of liberal political theory. Dr. Mills earned his Ph.D. from the University of Toronto. Currently a distinguished professor of philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York, he's previously taught at the University of Oklahoma, the University of Illinois in Chicago and Northwestern University. His first book, The Racial Contract, won a Gustavus Myers Outstanding Book Award for the study of bigotry and human rights in America. It's been adopted in hundreds of courses across the United States, including philosophy, political science, sociology, anthropology, literature, African American and American studies, among others. Of course, Dr. Mills's work can help us make sense out of the world we see today. He has described the current times as a complicated situation where we have both progress and regression, progress in that there is far more discussion in the public sphere, resulting from the activism of Black Lives Matter and protests of confederate statuary, and regression in the backlash from white Americans worried about losing their historically differentially privileged status. Dr. Mills's lecture today is titled Theorizing Racial Justice. Please help me welcome the 2020 Tanner Lecturer on Human Values, Dr. Charles W. Mills. (audience applauding) - [Charles Mills] Well, thank you so much to the organizers for this invitation. It was mentioned that my first degree is in physics, and I then switched to philosophy. The real reason was that in physics, you do actual experiments, and I found that they never came out the way I wanted, so you constantly have to fudge them. Well, the great virtue of philosophy is that you had to do thought experiments, and you then have complete control of the outcome. (audience laughing) So now, this was clearly the kind of discipline I have been waiting for. The physics thing was a big mistake. So in all seriousness, when I got this invitation, I was flattered, I felt honored, but I was also shocked because I thought of myself, you know, we like to sort of position ourselves with various delusions. I thought of myself as this radical oppositional guy, and I said, you know, radical oppositional guys don't give the Tanner Lectures. I mean, you know, that's something that's like a blot on your CV (audience laughing) so maybe I'll have to think this over. And then they mentioned the honorarium, and I said, well, okay, I guess I'll have to (audience laughing) I'll have to give up my principles just this once. Anyway, no, seriously, it is a real honor. It's wonderful to be here. Some of you may remember Clint Eastwood at the Academy Awards a few years ago talking to the absent figure of Barack Obama in a chair. As you just heard, John Rawls gave a lecture in this place some years ago, so perhaps on occasion you might find, is there an empty chair around? There is that one there. You might find me turning around to address him from time to time. (audience laughing) Okay, guys, so there is a detailed handout here, which you're really going to need, in part because there are, you know, diagrams, and so maybe that's part of my physics heritage. You know, they always told us, draw a diagram. So it'll help you to make sense of the whole thing. I'm going to talk for about 70 minutes, so the talk itself is longer than that, but I'll skip about a bit. But as I say, with the handout, you ought to be able to follow along. Okay, so my lecture this evening seeks to address the issue of racial justice, and in the process, to look also at the question has been so little addressed in Western, and more specifically, American political philosophy, for it is not as if the demand for racial justice is a new one. The protests of recent years, above all Black Lives Matter, have brought the topic solidly back onto the national agenda, effectively shattering the widespread post-racial society illusions that Barack Obama's 2008 election had encouraged. But of course, the demand is much older. I want to go back to the earlier civil rights movements of the 1950s and '60s, both mainstream and radical, or before that, to the debates around postbellum Reconstruction and the later disappointment and anger over the betrayal of Reconstruction or before that, during the epoch of slavery, to the long history of antebellum Abolitionism. And this list just focuses on blacks. I've not even said anything about Japanese internment, Chinese exclusion, anti-Latinx discrimination or returning to the founding colonial encounters, Native American expropriation and genocide. So the outcry against the inequitable treatment of people of color by whites, if not always under the explicit banner of racial justice, has in a sense always constituted the discordant counterpoint, the dissonantly off-key chorus, to what could be thought of as a self-congratulatory soundtrack, the approved theme music and national anthems, official and unofficial, of the republic, a republic that was, after all, effectively founded as, in a famous quote, a white man's country. And yet despite, or should that be because of this history and the larger history of modern Western imperialism and conquest in which it is embedded, white American political philosophers in particular and white Western political philosophers more generally have almost completely ignored the subject. But philosophers, at least in their own minds, are supposedly the professional experts, the go-to guys on questions of justice, stretching back 2,500 years to ancient Athens and the book often sorry, and the book often seen as the foundational text of the tradition, Plato's Republic. Moreover, the Western philosopher widely credited with reviving Anglo-American political philosophy, which had been judged very moribund at the time, was himself an American citizen, John Rawls. His famous 1971 book A Theory of Justice is standardly regarded not merely as reorienting the normative focus of his sub-discipline from the issue of our political obligation to the state to the issue of the justice of society's basic structure, but as making grand theory in the field possible again, as against boring logic chopping and linguistic analysis. Surely, then, the ideal conceptual and theoretical environment had now been created to talk about issues of racial justice, especially in the wake of 1960s protests and global postwar decolonization. It is emphasized, the topic is marginalized not just in Rawls, but in the vast secondary literature his work would generate over the next half-century, both Rawlsian and non-Rawlsian, including theorists on the right of the liberal spectrum and in non-liberal communitarian tradition as well. So though I'll be focusing on liberalism in general and Rawls in particular, that, oh, it's no longer an empty chair. Maybe somebody will have to bring an empty chair up on stage for me. It needs to be appreciated that the pattern of neglect in the field is much broader. So the lecture is going to be in three sections. In part one, illiberal liberalism, I will begin by locating this seemingly puzzling failure within a much longer history of liberal political philosophy's betrayal of its ostensible ideals. In part two, doing injustice to justice, how Rawls went wrong, I will then turn specifically to Rawls and the ways in which his particular version of the liberal social justice project was flawed from the start. Finally, in part three, liberal racial justice, I will indicate, if only sketchily, one possible strategy for deriving liberal principles of racial justice via a modified version of a famous Rawlsian thought experiment. Okay, guys, so section one, illiberal liberalism. So our starting point is a political philosophy of liberalism, but I need to quickly clarify that I'm using the word as a term of art, the way political philosophers and political theorists do. So liberalism does not refer just to the left wing of the Democratic Party, which we saw in action just last night, rather, its reference is the political ideology that developed over the 17th to 19th centuries in Western Europe in opposition to the doctrines of monarchical absolutism, natural socialist states, ascriptive social hierarchy, and inherited status. Associated with John Locke, Adam Smith, Thomas Paine, Thomas Jefferson, Immanuel Kant, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill and others, liberalism becomes the philosophy of the new social order, indeed, of modernity itself. The rule of law, limited government, democratic consent, individual equality, equal rights, all become the slogans of the revolt against the ancien regime. Hence, the American Revolution's famous opening statement of the Declaration, penned by Jefferson, we hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, and the liberty, equality, fraternity of the French Revolution. Being a liberal commits you to these broad principles. So from this perspective, we have liberals on the right who insist on market solutions and liberals on the left who argue for a state that intervenes on behalf of the disadvantaged, but by these minimal criteria, both groups count as liberals, hence conservatives' characterization of themselves sometimes as classical liberals. So we're the real liberals, you guys have usurped the title, you're really socialists. So liberalism can then be seen as the most important political ideology of the last few hundred years, the ideology that, especially after 1989, 1991, collapse of the East bloc, had seemingly emerged triumphant over all its challengers. As I don't have to tell you, the celebratory moment was pretty brief. We're now in a period when liberalism is under assault by right-wing populism and authoritarian ethno-nationalism, and there are no guarantees who will be the eventual victor. But certainly, we have to hope that liberalism will survive and eventually prevail, given the attractiveness of its ideals and the corresponding ugliness of those of its opponents. So in the official story, then, liberalism has historically faced foes both on the right and on the left, and has historically maintained a principled opposition to reactionary pre-modern ideologies, ideologies that deny people individual status and equal rights and entitlement to government by consent. It's a great story, an inspiring story. The problem is it happens to be untrue, or at least the extent to which it is true is severely qualified. Far from being in principled combat from the start against anti-egalitarian beliefs and systems of ascriptive hierarchy, liberalism has been complicit with many of them until comparatively recently, and some critics would say it is, in effect, if no longer overtly, still thus complicit today. Liberalism as ideal turns out to be illiberalism in actuality. Consider, for example, gender. From the first wave of feminism onward, for example, the British Mary Wollstonecraft's A Vindication of the Rights of Woman, the French Olympe de Gouges' Rights of Women, the U.S.'s own Abigail Adams, from the first wave, feminist theorists have pointed out that the promise of liberalism was not extended to women, a challenge that would, of course, be greatly deepened and expanded in the second wave and later waves. Denied equal rights, unable to own property or run for political office or even vote, their legal identities subsumed into their husbands under the doctrine of coverture, women are clearly not ranked among the free and equal individuals liberated by this new political philosophy of government by consent. Rather, their status seems to a kind of gender estate analogous to those subordinated in the feudal hierarchy. But women of all races constitute half the population to begin with. This is not a minor exclusion, but a huge one. Then think of race. Though this history is now marginalized in the official liberal story, we need to remember that most of the Western European states now uncontroversially considered part of the liberal West at one time or another had empires, British, French, Dutch, Spanish, Portuguese, Belgian, in which non-Europeans, indigenous peoples, and in some cases African slaves, were systemically subordinated. Together, these Western countries ruled undemocratically over the vast majority of humanity. Indeed, this global racial inequality was so firmly entrenched as a norm, so taken for granted, if I am giving this historical episode at numerous talks I have given, I sometimes ask the audience, how many of you have heard of this, and usually it's very few hands that grow. 1919, so a bit more than a century ago, when the post-World War One Versailles Conference in Paris to set up the League of Nations, just had this horrible war, the Great War, want to make sure this never happens again. We all know how successful they were at that. Most of the world is colonized. Most of the world is under the rule of European powers. One of the few independent nations of color is Japan. The Japanese delegation says, hey, we need a racial equality clause in the Covenant of the League of Nations so as to make sure that we have a world that's racially equitable. Nothing controversial about equality. After all, as I just said earlier, equality is supposedly one of the watchwords of liberal modernity. And we're now deep into liberal modernity. I mean, for God's sake, it's the 20th century. And this proposal by the Japanese was unequivocally rejected by the six Anglo-Saxon nations, as they were then called. And who, you might ask, were they? Britain, the United States, Canada, Australia, New Zealand, and South Africa. So let me ask you guys, how many of you have ever heard of his historical episode. A handful. This in a prestigious, very well-known University of Michigan and has not been part of your education, and you need to ask yourself why that is, what that says about the educational system that, you know, you were inculcated with and what that says about the sort of broader history of imperialism and colonialism that has now been covered up. Anyway, so then that's gender, that's race. Think now of class. Though modernity is surely supposed, at the very least, to equalize status hierarchies among white males, even here the process is very uneven. The birth of liberalism may date to the 17th century, but property restrictions on the franchise in many European countries remain in place to the late 19th and early 20th centuries. And the US, it's really only with 19th century Jacksonian democracy that you get universal suffrage even among white men. So the point is then that once we put together all the exclusions of actual historical liberalism, we should be able to see that a conceptualization that represents them as anomalies and deviations is fundamentally wrong. The dominant varieties of historical liberalism excluded the majority of the world's population from equal normative consideration. But if exclusion is modal, if propertied white males are the major beneficiaries of modernity's liberalization, then how can the conventional narrative of a clear transition from the world of hierarchical estates to a world of equal individuals be sustained? Doesn't our periodization, doesn't our conceptual map and our temporal map need to be changed? And happily for you, you don't have to do this yourself because on this very useful handout, if you can see it in this dark room, a little bit lighter in here, I have provided for you a neat diagram which you can put on your, I don't know, your bathroom wall, your refrigerator door, the place where you do your heavy thinking. So the top indicates the conventional story. So the conventional periodization is illiberalism versus liberalism. So illiberalism is premodern, inegalitarian political ideologies, such as you'd find in ancient Greece and Rome, such as you'd find in the Middle Ages. Those are the bad old days, when you had people who were in these sort of hierarchical social orders, citizens and slaves in ancient Greece and Rome, lords and serfs in the Middle Ages, but thank God that's all over. We're now in the modern period. We've put all that behind. We're now in the world of individuals. So that's a just so story. That's a fairy story that you tell your kids, or at last, perhaps, that you tell your students. Maybe you guys, some of you guys right here in this room have heard this story. So the bottom diagram, the revisionist periodization, gives the more accurate story. So in that story, we should sort of see it as illiberalism part one, and then illiberalism part two, and illiberalism part two is for some reason known as liberalism. So in illiberalism part one, we have the hierarchies I mentioned and also gender hierarchies, which at least until recently, were not part of the story. As feminists have pointed out, you can see woman as constituting a kind of subordinate gender estate. So citizens and slaves in ancient Greece and Rome and men and women, medieval period, lords and serfs, and again men and women, and then in the modern period, lo and behold, we continue to have these hierarchies, men and women still, it's a sort of, you know, enduring constant. There's also the property and non-property insofar as the restriction on the franchise and stuff like that, and we have the new category of whites over people of color. So by the conventional dating, you don't have race in the pre-modern period, it's only in modernity that race comes into existence. So the point is that with this reconceptualization, we would re-theorize liberalism to emphasize its continuity with the past rather than its putative sharp break from it. And we would then start to look at liberalism very differently, with, shall we say, a far more suspicious and critical eye. So rather than automatically presuming that liberalism is going to be adequate to dealing with a particular social problem facing us, we would begin by asking ourselves the question, if liberalism has been illiberalism along so many crucial axes of social subordination, how has this pernicious shaping by group domination affected its crucial concepts, norms, frameworks and assumptions? What silences, what opacities, what inadequacies might we expect to find in liberalism given this history? Indeed, isn't it likely to be the case that where class, gender, and race are involved, the inclusion of groups previously formally excluded is going to be merely nominal unless the deep structuring of liberalism as a theory by its previous history is acknowledged and expressly addressed? So one can readily appreciate, then, why given this history, some radical political political thinkers have given up on liberalism together, and has also given up on people like Charles Mills, who still insist that liberalism can break free. So now there's a bunch of folks who cross the street when they see me coming. What can I say, guys. I hope you won't join their company because I'm going to sort of defend here a radical liberalism. And not to plug my recent book, but that's what these occasions are in part for, right? So my recent book, Black Rights, White Wrongs, one of the themes of the book is black radical liberalism. So if this sounds oxymoronic, you know, a bad book, available at all better bookstore, oh, they don't exist, available at Amazon, and you sort of, you know, get my attempt to sort of combine radical theory with liberalism. Okay, so anyway, how can you retrieve liberalism given this sordid history and given these critiques? My claim is that rather than, you know, sort of brushing all this stuff, you know, under the carpet, to liberalize illiberal liberalism, we need to do several things, number one, rewrite the history of liberalism so its exclusions are highlighted rather than marginalized, number two, make clear rather than obfuscate the role of the canonical liberal theorists in justifying these exclusions, number three, place at center stage rather than offstage the concrete shaping by group privilege of the crucial components of liberalism, and then number four, self-consciously reconceive all of these to achieve genuine liberal justice. So my claim is that if you make these moves, you can get a liberalism that's quite different from the ones that we're accustomed to, the liberalism that, as I say, has been complicit with these systems of ascriptive hierarchy that were supposed to be eliminated by the transition to the modern period. Okay, so on that basis, then, I suggest that we sort of look at the components of liberalism and come up with what I see as a list, so this is on page two of the handout, of crucial components, A, a characteristic set of value commitments, that's, you know, moral equality, freedom and self-realization, B, a certain social ontology, if you're a member of the American Philosophical Association and you don't use the word ontology in a talk, there's somebody at the APA sitting at the back row, and your membership card will be yanked. (audience laughing) So you always have to make sure that ontology's in there. Okay, so whoever it is, I have put ontology in there. (audience laughing) So B, a certain social ontology, C, a conceptual cartography of the socio-political, D, an account of the history that has led up to the present, and C, a schedule of rights, protections, and freedoms. So value commitment, that should be straightforward. Social ontology, what do I mean? How do we think of people in liberal political philosophy? And liberalism is traditionally thought of as has an ontology of atomic individuals. And I will claim that this conventional representation is actually false, because there are liberal theorists, and Derrick Darby, my friend, I was going to say my colleague, but that's not my colleague in the sense of, you know, black philosophers, my colleague has pointed out that there's a tradition of T.H. Green and the British Hegelians, and they had a liberalism that was social, or if you look at in the United States, John Dewey's liberalism is very much a social one, and what I would argue, and people like Elizabeth Anderson have argued for this, there's no inconsistency in saying that in a society based on domination, we need a social ontology that registers the fact of domination. So we can't assume that everybody is effectively equal if some people are positioned above others, so you need a social ontology that registers the fact of group domination, whether men over women, whites over people of color or what. C, conceptual cartography, what do I mean? Well, think of, you know, the second-wave feminist critique that the way the polity is drawn, the way the public-private boundary is drawn, is that, you know, the distinctive problems of women are basically not allowed to enter into the public sphere. So the family, patriarchal relations, sex, all of that is part of the private sphere. That's not a matter of justice. So what, you know, second-wave feminists sort of set themselves to do is to argue for the redrawing of that map. So the conceptual cartography, how we draw the polity, that matters. D, the history, what I mean there is that to consider issues of, you know, how this society came into being, issues perhaps of corrective justice. We need to know what the actual history is. And part of the problem with actual liberal theory is that it obfuscates, it covers up, it whitewashes the history, the history which as I sort of mentioned briefly earlier, has been a history of racial subordination. So all of those put together, if you rewrite them, you rewrite the ontology, you remap the cartography, you have a different account of the history, it then means that to sort of bring about equality, freedom and self-realization for individuals, you could end up with principles which seem quite different from liberal principles, but they're still liberal, but this is a liberalism that has now taken the history of the society and the actual structure of the society into account in a way that mainstream liberalism has not. So on the axis of class, going back to the 19th century, you have a social democratic version of liberal theory, which says that liberal principles are okay, but we need to sort of face the fact that the working class is going to be materially subordinated unless you sort of take account of the differential power that capital has. I don't have to tell you we're now in an epoch, one percent versus the 99 percent, the rise of plutocracy, as it has been called the third Gilded Age, it was Mark Twain's Gilded Age in the 19th century, or the 1920s, also known as the Jazz Age, we're now in the third Gilded Age, and people like Thomas Piketty have argued this may be the longest lasting one of all. So the inequalities of wealth in the United States and other countries are sort of as large as they've ever been. So there's a social democratic critique, well-established. The gender critique, the feminist critique, again, you need to sort of recognize the extent to which, you know, men are dominant over women, and this, you know, patriarchal domination manifests itself in all kinds of spheres. And of course, we've had several decades of feminist theory laying out a very plausible case to this effect. But the point I would make is that unfortunately, the racial critique has not been as well-developed as these other critiques, so that what I am arguing for that we need to do is develop a racial critique of liberal theory that is going to be comparable in its significance and, you know, for the importance of rewriting mainstream political philosophy and mainstream political theory as, you know, social democratic liberal theory and feminist liberal theory have been. Okay, let me now talk briefly about what I'm going to call a liberalism that's racial, and the term here is unfortunately a bit confusing in that if, in the 1950s, somebody said you were racial liberal, it meant you were somebody who thought you should support black civil rights, you should oppose segregation, in other words, you're a good guy. You know, we want people to be racial liberals. Had I know that the term was so solidly entrenched in this previous use, I might not have employed it. Anyway, I'm trying to demarcate a separate usage. And racial liberalism, as I use the term, is basically a liberalism that has been shaped by racial domination. So think of racial liberalism as analogous to what feminists would see as a patriarchal form of liberal theory, where liberalism has been shaped by its evolution in societies of male domination, so it then means that crucial terms, crucial frameworks, crucial values have all been permeated by the fact of male domination and the need to justify the subordination of half of the human race. And I'm arguing for a racial liberalism that's comparable to a patriarchal liberalism and that evolves in the period of European expansionism when key liberal theorists are completely on board with this program, so that Europeans basically expand into the world, and you cannot then apply liberal theories equally to people of color as you can to Europeans because then obviously, it would mean that the processes in which you are involved, your conquest of peoples, expropriation, racial slavery, these are all inconsistent with a liberalism that, you know, is color inclusive, so it has to be a liberalism that's racially restrictive. So we get a liberalism that's racialized. So it's a racial liberalism in that sense, in that crucial terms of the liberal theory are rewritten by race so that the privileging of Europeans at the expense of people of color does not seem like an inconsistent does not seem like an inconsistency because people of color are not seen as moral equals. So you then get the world that I described, you know, in the Versailles Conference, where the Japanese proposal is shot down because, you know, the Anglo-Saxon nations are basically saying, look, the colonial world rests on racial inequality, this principle would upend this world, so clearly, we cannot have that as part of the Covenant of the League of Nations. Okay, so the crucial question then is given that liberalism has been racialized, why is it there has not been more discussion within political theory and political philosophy of this fact? Why has this not been a sort of self-conscious project to sort of explore and investigate the racialization of liberalism and then to sort of make the theoretical moves necessary to deracialize it? And my argument here, and some people have objected to this, but tell me what you think. My argument here is that one major factor is the demographic whiteness of the profession. So this will come as no news to the philosophers in the room. To the non-philosophers, let me break the news to you. As I don't have to tell you, people of color are underrepresented in the academy in general. In philosophy, it's so extreme that basically, if you go to a meeting of the American Philosophical Association, you have to put on dark glasses, otherwise you might get snow blindness (audience laughing) from the sort of expanse of white faces. The percentage of black people in philosophy, I am not making this up. It sounds like I am, but I am not. The percentage of black philosophers in philosophy is one percent. It was one percent 20 years ago. It's still one percent today. Latinos, maybe another one percent. Asian-Americans, another one percent. Native Americans, basically fingers of two hands. It's about three percent people of color, very white profession. And the demographic whiteness, I would argue, basically helps to sustain a conceptual whiteness. And this term might seem more controversial, because the demographic whiteness is just a matter of numbers. You know, hard to disagree with that. The conceptual whiteness, you have to make more of a case for, because many white philosophers get their backs up and they say, look, philosophy can't be white because philosophy is dealing with the human condition, people of color are human, you're sort of not denying that, therefore, you know, you guys are automatically included in the sort of, you know, general and abstract representations that we're giving you as philosophers. And the problem with the argument, which feminist philosophers have sort of also made the case, you know, for the maleness of philosophy, is that the distinctive experiences of people of color are not really accommodated within these seemingly general and all-inclusive abstractions. So as I just mentioned, the experience of people of color in modernity is an experience of colonization, imperialist subordination, expropriation, racial slavery, apartheid, Jim Crow. To what extent are these experiences really part of the standard political story we hear in political philosophy? And I would argue they're almost completely marginal. So the question then is what can be done about this? Well, before I move to that, which of course is the climax of the whole thing, let me make some comments about John Rawls. Okay, so I might might have brought they are still not, okay so pretend he's sitting there. So Clint Eastwood at the Academy Awards, I am talking to John Rawls. Professor Rawls, who I should emphasize I never met, and I should also emphasize that everybody I've known who has met him speaks very highly of him, and tomorrow you'll hear from two of his students, so it should be emphasized that I'm it's not talking about I've had bad experience with Rawls, I'm just talking about Rawls as a representative of a particular group in a particular time period positioned in such a way that certain problems are not addressed. So it seems to focus on Rawls, but I'm really talking about an entire cohort of white mainstream political theorists. Okay, so Rawls's 1971 book A Theory of Justice is generally seen by many people as the most important book in political philosophy of the 20th century. Well, it's certainly the most American book in political philosophy of the 20th century, but some people go further, the most important book of global political philosophy of the 20th century. And this book accomplishes several things. It revives social contract theory. Social contract theory had its heyday in the century and a half from 1650 to 1800, so Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Immanuel Kant. And then it goes into historical decline. It's displaced by more historically oriented theories like Hegel and later Marx, and by utilitarian theory. And you know, by the mid-'50s or so, social contract theory is seen as dead, and also Anglo-American political philosophy is seen as moribund. You know, if you go back to the period, you find articles written, you know, sort of worrying about the survival of Anglo-American political philosophy. And the subject matter was seen as so boring that it's not merely that the people reading the articles tended to fall asleep, even the people writing the articles tended to fall asleep. (audience laughing) You know, you are there so, what was I writing again, oh, right, right. So political philosophy (audience laughing) had been reduced to boring stuff like linguistic analysis, how should we think of obligation and so forth. And Rawls's work revitalizes the field. And suddenly people are doing all kinds of exciting stuff. They are talking about, you know, the big picture, the grand theory and so forth. And one of the crucial things that Rawls does, he revives social contract theory, and he says the appropriate theme of social contract theory should be social justice. And here is what Rawls does. He revives social contract theory in the form of a thought experiment. As I mentioned to you guys, I switched from physics because my real life experiments in the lab, they never came out, but thought experiments, that was a whole different story. So here is a Rawlsian thought experiment. You're going to be choosing principles of justice for a society, and you're choosing them not on principled moral grounds but on selfish grounds, prudential grounds, what's in it for me? And you might think, that's a really bad basis for choosing principles of justice, but you haven't heard the whole story because Rawls specifies you're choosing behind a veil of ignorance, so you don't know crucial facts about yourself, you don't know crucial facts about the society, so it means that the combination of self-interest and the stipulated ignorance is going to result in the equivalent of a moral choice. And Rawls also allows for a sort of move out from behind the veil and check what these principles, whether or not they comport with all sort of deepest, you know, moral principles, so a sort of check of that kind. So you're not going to choose a sexist society because for all you know, you may turn out to be female. You're not going to choose a racist society because for all you know, you may turn out to be white, not of course, that there can't be other kinds of racist societies. You're not going to choose a plutocratic society because you don't know whether you're going to be in the privileged socio-economic class. So Rawls says these are a good way for generating principles of justice, and the principles he came up with, I have written down for you, so I hope you have your handouts with you, in the form of a neat formula that I originally devised to sort of help my students to remember what the principles were, and they're BL arrow FEO arrow DP. And what that stands for are principles of distributive justice for an ideal society, because the crucial point about Rawls is that he said our focus should be devising principles of justice for an ideal, that's a perfect society, a well-ordered society. So there are two principles of justice. The first principle, BL, those are the basic rights and liberties people should have, for example, to vote, to run for office, you have freedom of speech, liberty of conscience, right to hold personal property, all that good stuff. Second principle has two components, FEO, fair equality of opportunity, that's a combination of formal equality of opportunity, so you know, people are not discriminated against when applying for jobs and so forth, but in addition, resources sort of equalized for class disadvantage. So the idea would be if you're a working class kid as against an upper class kid, you should not be disadvantaged by that class background. We want you to have an equal shot at it for people who are, you know, sort of equally able. And then finally, difference principle, that's for people who are disadvantaged by other things, for example, you have a thin bundle of natural talents. Rawls was a guy who believed there's a sort of definite sort of distribution curve of talents. Okay, so Rawls's book would generate a huge body of secondary literature, but here's the problem. He had very little to say about corrective justice. These are principles of distributive justice for an ideal society, a perfect society. And racial justice, my theme for this evening, is largely a matter of corrective justice in societies that are unjust. So in my work in previous years, I have spent a fair amount of time criticizing Rawls and Rawlsians and saying, look, you guys claim to be concerned about justice, and yet you're not talking about racial justice, we need to sort of ask the question about how we can make the transition from Rawls's principles of ideal justice for a well-ordered society to societies that are not well-ordered, we need to talk about corrective justice. And then about two years ago, I had a theoretical epiphany. So there are religious epiphanies. There are all kinds of epiphanies. There are Protestant epiphanies. This was a theoretical epiphany. And I came to believe that actually, I had been misinterpreting Rawls all along, and what that implied is that a significant amount of my previous criticisms of Rawls had been unjustified. But you'll be glad to hear, lest you think it's going to turn to a sort of Rawls lovefest, that it meant that a whole new wave of criticisms could now be unleashed. (audience laughing) So I'm going to give you the background to sort of explain this, and I have a claim that I've put in bold, I don't know if you can see it in this room, but here is my dramatic claim, put in bold. Rawls's theory of justice does not apply to the United States. Let me say that again because it's so bizarre. Rawls's theory of justice does not apply to the United States. So obviously, you're going to ask, why on Earth would Rawls, a citizen of United States, have devised a theory of justice that was not applicable to his own country? But I'm not saying he intended it not to apply. Rather, what I claim is that as a matter of fact it doesn't apply. So in analytic philosophy, it's standardly accused of having physics envy. So you see, I mean, I switched from physics into philosophy not realizing I was not getting away from physics. Anyway, so part of the physics envy manifests itself in the use of, you know, diagrams and subscripts and letters and so forth, so again, to sort of keep my APA membership, I've done my small bit towards this end, so once more, if you consult your handout, you would see my original interpretation and now my revised interpretation. So my original interpretation, and I'm suggesting that the first three premises of this are widely shared in the profession. It is important to phi. We should be trying to phi. Rawls is trying to phi. Rawls is doing a bad job of phiing, bad Rawls, bad. So Rawls should be criticized for doing a bad job of phiing, and in fact, that's what I have been doing for several years. How wrong I was. My recent revised interpretation, Rawls is not trying to phi in the first place, so Rawls cannot be criticized for phiing badly. But it's important to phi. We should be trying to phi. So Rawls should be criticized for not even trying to phi in the first place. So the obvious question, the burning question that I know you all have on your lips is, well, gee, what is phiing? And not to keep you in suspense, the answer is phiing is developing a theory of justice for modern Western societies of all kinds, both racist and non-racist. And why is Rawls not trying to phi? Because in his own mind, he doesn't have to. The class of racist modern Western societies is empty. No modern Western society is racist, therefore the United States is not racist. Now, that's a pretty strange set of claims. So let me now try to make them plausible for you. So I'm going to use the symbol TJR and not R. Rawls's theory of justice applies both to racist and non-racist Western societies. TJ not R, Rawls's theory of justice only applies to non-racist Western societies. USA not R, the the US is not a racist society. USA R, the US is a racist society. So let's go through these. And first of all, where is the evidence for this crucial claim I made, which is obviously quite crazy? My suggestion is that it's in his final book, Justice as Fairness. So this is the last book Rawls wrote, not quite finished because of his illness, edited by philosopher Erin Kelly. And in this book, you can find the following two sentences, admittedly separated by some pages, but nonetheless, I think the link should be clear. Page 14, so this is John Rawls. Justice as fairness, so that's Rawls's theory, justice as fairness is a political conception of justice for the special case of the basic structure of a modern democratic society. And then a few pages later, page 21, he expands on this. From the start, then, with your democratic society as a political society that excludes a confessional or an aristocratic state, not to mention a caste, slave, or racist one. So this was my epiphany. It's not that I was reading this book for the first time. The book has been out since, like, you know, 2001. But for some reason, the passages had never struck me before. So my inference is that Rawls is saying, look, my theory has a very limited scope. It doesn't apply to these other theories, you know, and you wouldn't think of them, you know, confessional, that's a theocratic state, aristocratic state, caste society, racist society included on that list. So the question then is am I getting things wrong, because you see, if I am not getting things wrong, then the natural follow-up question is how come nobody has noticed this before? As I say, this is not a new book. Justice as Fairness came out in 2001. A lot of people read Rawls's work, so a lot of people have read these passages. So could it be that I've just misinterpreted these passages? So in this section, I tried to consider some objections to my theory, and I am doubtless Professor Freeman will have even more tomorrow that I have not thought of, unfortunately, and say why I don't think those objections work. Okay, objection number one. You, Charles Mills, are just confusing and misreading the familiar distinction Rawls makes between ideal theory, that's the theory of a perfectly just society, and non-ideal theory. So he's not saying anything new than, you know, what he's always said. Here is my response to that. If that were true, it would then mean that Rawls's theory of justice applies to all the other societies in that list. All you have to do is to switch to the non-ideal extrapolation of Rawls's theory. So that list includes, just to remind you, a confessional state, that's a theocratic state, an aristocratic state, a caste society, a slave society. But the problem with this is that everybody knows in the profession who reads Rawls in political philosophy that Rawls's work is marked by a shift in the early Rawls to the later Rawls from what seems like an all-encompassing theory, a comprehensive liberal theory, to a political liberal theory, and he makes clear what he said was there in the early work is badly phrased. His reference point is modern Western liberal democracies. So it's not the case that Rawls's theory is all-applicable, that can be sort of, you know, you can apply it to all kinds of societies. It's limited to modern Western liberal societies. So my response a reductio of the claim that you know, you can just switch to non-ideal theory and apply it to racist societies, because if that were true, that would go for the others also, and that goes against what we know and is well-established in the secondary literature, that's not how Rawls meant his work to be read. So consider a second objection. The second objection now is, okay, maybe you're right, but it's an isolated element of his, of what he says, In other words, Rawls was sick, it's an isolated conceptual gaffe, and you know, had he had the time to sort of do a proper revision of his work, it's something he would have cleared up. So it might be true, he might have said it, but it's not really something that's related to the rest of his work. And I suggest that far from this being true, it follows directly from the characterization he gives from the very opening pages of A Theory of Justice. And part of the problem is that these pages have not been as read as thoroughly as they should have been despite the fact that at the start of the book, I mean, you can sort of start to skip and skim later in the book, but surely not in the opening pages, so everybody who reads Rawls will have read those pages. And what does he say in those pages? What he says explicitly is that society is, and here I quote, a cooperative venture for mutual advantage governed by rules designed to advance the good of those taking part in it. He's not given us a definition of an ideal, well-ordered society. That doesn't come until the next paragraph. He's telling us what a society is. So Rawls is basically defining society in such a way that only societies of equity and cooperation and reciprocal benefit count as societies. And that's kind of crazy, and it's also inconsistent with what we just heard where he does concede the existence of theocratic societies, slave societies, aristocratic societies, and so forth. So I think the most charitable reading of, you know, this characterization of societies in A Theory of Justice is that Rawls is telling us, these are the societies to which my theory of justice applies. So there's a range of possible societies, you know, all kinds of different societies, obvious throughout human history, these are the societies to which my theory applies. And what I think gives plausibility to my interpretation is that, remember, Rawls not merely revives Anglo-American political philosophy, but he revives social contract theory. And the key idea of social contract theory is that we should think of society as having been formed by people in a pre-social and pre-political condition coming together to say, let's create a society, let's create a political order, and let's make sure that, you know, we don't lose, we don't sort of overall lose out the advantages we have by being in a pre-social and pre-political so-called state of nature. In the state of nature, you have all kinds of freedoms, but there's a danger, especially in theorists like Hobbes, you're going to be ripped off. So we want the state to protect us, so we sort of give up some freedoms and sort of have others safeguarded, where the crucial point is that it's a consensual process, and what you're going to establish is a society and a political system that benefits everybody. So once you think of it that way, you see that he's telling us from the start, my theory has a very limited application, my theory only applies to societies that can be modeled by the social contract metaphor. And unfortunately, given the unhappy history of humanity, that is a very, very small subset of the societies that have existed in human history. In fact, you could go so far as to say that given the history of all kinds of oppression, gender oppression, ethnic oppression, religious oppression, colonial oppression, racial oppression, maybe it only applies to hunter-gatherer societies, that once you get class society emerging, once you get patriarchy emerging, once you get, you know, the early stages of colonialism, all these societies are going to be oppressive, Rawls's theory does not apply to them because none of these societies can be modeled by the social contract of being brought into existence in a consensual way with rules that are going to benefit everybody. So my suggestion is that, far from this being any isolated conceptual gaffe, it's in fact tied directly to the specification he's given three decades earlier of the kinds of societies to which his principles apply. And then finally, the third objection, look, here's why you have to be wrong. Your implication would then be that Rawls could say nothing about race because, you know, you would have a situation where you have a racist society, he's excluded it, but we know that Rawls does talk about race, not at any great length, but there are scattered passages here and there. He cites Martin Luther King, Jr., and in Justice as Fairness, his final book, he expresses his hope that liberal principles will be able to tackle issues of gender and racial injustice. So what you're saying, Mills, could not be true because if Rawls did not expect his theory could extend to racist societies, he would not have said explicitly that I am confident that the principles of the liberal tradition will be able to handle these issues. I have not done so myself, nonetheless, I'm sure they can. And here is where I argue, this is part of my epiphany, here is where I argue we need to make a crucial distinction between societies with racism and societies that are racist. And my argument is going to be that Rawls thought of the US as a society with racism but not a society that is racist. And to this end, I'm going to call your attention to this incomprehensible diagram that is occupying a full page in your handout. And my hope is that if you bear with me, I will make it comprehensible. So this large I at the left, I stands for ideal, because remember, Rawls's principles of justice are for ideal societies, what he calls well-ordered societies, that's what his principles are for. So on the left you have ideal. And then as you move right, as you move away from the left, I didn't design it that way, folks, not to reveal my political sympathies, it's just the way left and right work out, as you move to the right, you move away from ideality, and the further you get over here, the further you are from an ideal society. So if you are here, you're almost perfect, an almost perfect society, whereas if you're over here, you're in a deeply oppressive social system. So here's the point, and an obvious point when you think about it that has not been sufficiently paid attention to by political philosophers. The category of the non-ideal encompasses a huge range of societies because the ideal, in the literal sense, means perfect, so the slightest deviation from perfection immediately precipitates you into the realm of the non-ideal. So societies that are just to the right of this big I, that are almost perfect, and societies way over here are in the same category of the non-ideal. Now, clearly, that is a very crude category. That's a very undifferentiated category. It's not going to work for us. We need to make an internal distinction within the realm of the ideal. So this dotted line that I've indicated here is supposed to indicate the transition between societies that are basically pretty good overall, they're not perfect, but they're still pretty good, and then once you cross this dotted line, you get into the area of societies that are not merely non-ideal, but they're oppressive. Okay, so this box, society is non-ideal but non-oppressive, whereas everything over here from then on is non-ideal and oppressive. And my suggestion is that the social contract metaphor of a society as a cooperative venture of mutual advantage with reciprocally beneficial rules, that only applies to societies in what I am calling the I zone, within the dotted area. So they're not perfect, but they're close enough that we can say, yeah, they're roughly roughly societies that can be modeled by a contract. And once you pass the dotted line, once you're in this part of the diagram, the contract metaphor no longer applies. So the crucial question then is, for the issue of race, where does the United States fit? Okay, so that brings us to the sort of crucial question of how should we think of the United States historically? Is it merely a society with racism, or is it a society that is itself racist? Okay, so what I suggest is that, though Rawls never went into this, and because mainstream political philosophers don't talk about race, you know, it has not been investigated by them, either, what is the difference, what is the principal demarcation, from a Rawlsian point of view, between a society with racism and a society that is racist? And so the principal demarcation is, does race affect, in a deep and significant way, the basic structure? It's a crucial concept for Rawls. He says justice applies to the basic structure, and that's what we should focus on. And the basic structure includes the main political and social institutions, so that's the Constitution, it's an independent judicial system, the legally recognized forms of property and the structure of the economy, the family. That's all in the basic structure. So the crucial question for us is, does race affect any of these in a way that's deep and significant, because if it does, you then have a racialized basic structure. So let's consider the possibilities. So I have them sort of listed on the handout for you. Could it be that the United States was racist before Rawls's birth, but then ceased to be one by the time of his birth? Could it be that it was racist during his lifetime for part of it, but then ceased to be such? Could it be that it was racist during his lifetime, but after, not? So I go through all of them, and I ask you to think of the following, and bear in mind some of you, I'm sure, will have read the 1619 Project, you know, that people on The New York Times undertook, and the crucial point of how, fundamentally, slavery has shaped the United States and continues to do so 400 years later. And you may also have read of the controversy, there are some historians pushing back, but what's important to emphasize is that the push-back is on secondary issues, for example, the claim that they make that the revolution against the British was in part to protect slavery. So there's push-back on those claims, but the crucial claim, on which there's pretty well agreement across the board, is that slavery has deeply shaped the United States. Okay, so consider first of all the period before Rawls's birth. The US was a slave society. Rawls talks about legally recognized forms of property. This included property in human beings. And there's a famous historian of slavery, died a few years ago, Ira Berlin, celebrated as one of American slavery's leading historians, and he drew a famous distinction between, quote, societies with slaves where slavery was institutionally siloed, it's sort of cabined, and then slave societies, where the peculiar institution, so-called in the US, pervades, directly or indirectly, the whole social order. So in effect, the entire society is peculiar. And for him, the United States was a prime example of the latter. So a quote here from Berlin. Slavery stood at the center of economic production, and the master-slave relationship provided the model for all social relations, husband and wife, parent and child, employer and employee, teacher and student, end quote. So the structure of the economy was a structure of a slave economy. So clearly, there is no ambiguity there. During the period of slavery, there is no doubt at all that the basic structure insofar as the economy, the crucial part of it, the basic structure is racialized. Well, what about the Constitution? Again, scholars of the Constitution have pointed out that, you know, you find slavery affecting how the Constitution is written, and there are all these clauses where slavery is not mentioned, but they're basically referring indirectly to the institution of slavery. And then even after the war, 13th, 14th, 15th Amendments, the Civil War amendments, there's a question of how the Constitution is interpreted. So Rawls is giving us, in effect, a kind of naive picture, there's a Constitution, there's one set of interpretations, so we don't need to worry about the Constitution and so on. But how are the principles of the Constitution interpreted? So for example, think of the Equal Protection Clause of the 14th Amendment. It's an Equal Protection Clause, so clearly that's going to rule out the institution of Jim Crow, because the system of separate but equal is clearly unfair to black Americans. Well, it didn't, that's the whole point. In the Plessy versus Ferguson decision of 1896, the Supreme Court ruled that you could, in fact, have separate but equal, and that's not overturned, of course, as we know, until the decision of Brown. So whatever the Constitution says, it's always subject to interpretation, which is why there's a debate between people who think we should go for original intent and people who think we should side with the idea of a living Constitution that evolves over time. So merely to point to an attractive principle in the Constitution is not sufficient. The question is how these principles are interpreted. Okay, so the period before Rawls's birth, US was clearly a racist society, during the period of slavery. What about the period of Jim Crow? Well, again, think about it. It's the period of the betrayal of Reconstruction, separate but equal, which is really separate and unequal, thousands of unpunished lynchings, the repeated defeat in Congress of attempted anti-lynching legislation, and in general, widespread discrimination, reducing blacks to the status of second-class members of the social system. A slave economy has been replaced by a Jim Crow economy, and there's a famous essay by the legal theorist Cheryl Harris suggests that whiteness effectively functions as property. So even if you don't have formal slavery, you have property in whiteness, and that means again that property relations have been affected by race. And here's a really, a really stunning fact, a really ugly fact, but something that, again, people need to know. It's the 1930s. You're a young Nazi lawyer. You know, the Third Reich is being put in place. You're looking forward to a glorious thousand-year history, and you want to disenfranchise the Jewish population. You're looking for a juridical model for the Nuremberg Laws, the 1935 anti-Semitic Nuremberg Laws, which reduced Jews to second-class status. And if people will forgive a bit of national stereotype and you are German, you want to do things thoroughly and properly, so you look all arounds the world for a role model, and which society do you hit upon? Alas, it's United States. Book came out in 2017, Hitler's model, Hitler's legal model, something like that, Jim Crow legislation in the United States was a model the Nazis used for the anti-Semitic Nuremberg Laws. And people may be interested in who the runner-up was in the sort of competition for the supreme racial state on the planet. The runner-up was the British Empire. So again, probably not part of the history you were taught in high school or even in university. This is a racial history, the centrality of race to making of the modern world that people like myself, people in critical race theory says we need to talk about it more because it's so crucial to understanding the world that we currently have. Okay, so clearly, you know, the period before Rawls's birth, that was not a period where you could say that the basic structure is not affected by race. So maybe it's in Rawls's lifetime. Maybe it's what was called the second Reconstruction. First Reconstruction didn't work out so well. We had the betrayal of Reconstruction. We had the withdrawal of federal troops. We had, you know, the rollback of voting rights. But the second Reconstruction, civil rights legislation in the 1950s and '60s, maybe that's the turning point, that from then on, you could say the US was not racist. But again, looking back from the perspective of 40, 50 years later, those of us who work on race know the unhappy statistics, continuing residential segregation, continuing educational segregation, ongoing nationwide practice of de facto discrimination, new techniques of disenfranchisement, voter suppression, the wealth gap, the prison-industrial complex, the pattern of police killings of unarmed black men and women, it's not really plausible to claim that the US has ceased to be a racist society. And finally, because discussions of the family, because the family is probably like the basic structure for Rawls, discussions of the family in the Rawlsian literature, because of the demography of the profession, have been overwhelmingly shaped by the interests of white feminist theory. But if we look at the family from the perspective of black women, Latina women, native women, then the family is also racialized as an institution. During slavery, obviously, slave families were not recognized, and even free black families were not seen as equal to the white ones. Dorothy Roberts, well-known black feminist theorist, points out a long history of black women and women of color being deprived of equal reproductive rights. If you think of anti-miscegenation law, if you think of the fact that in a liberal democracy, the Constitution allowed states to forbid people from being involved in interracial relations, interracial marriages, and that it took until 1967, the Supreme Court Loving versus Virginia decision, and that at one time or another, not at the same time, but at different times, at one time or another, no less than 41 states had anti-miscegenation legislation on the books, so that as one theorist has pointed out, you would see anti-miscegenation law as a kind of factory for the production of race. So it means that by all these criteria, the economy, the polity, the legal system, the family, the basic structure has been racialized from the start. So if you use the criterion of the basic structure being affected by race in a deep and significant way, then the US is a racist society, and in then follows that Rawls's principles do not apply to the United States. So what are the implications of this? They are really very startling. To begin with the obvious point, it means that if you are attempting to use Rawls's work to do to basically theorize corrective racial justice, you can't because it means that corrective racial justice, for Rawls, would only be for societies within the I zone, within that sort of small space close to ideal societies. Societies that are outside the I zone, you need a different set of principles for them. So that's one obvious set of implications. But there's an even more startling set of implications. Even if you're not working on race, whatever you're working on, if you're applying if you're trying to apply Rawls to the United States, whatever area you're working on, the implication of this, as I say, this epiphany I've had, is that you cannot do that either because Rawls's principles in general do not apply to the United States, whether you're working on race or not. So next year, 2021, 50th anniversary of Rawls's book, it would mean, if I am right, that half a century of Rawls scholarship, insofar as that scholarship has sought to apply it to the United States, half a century of Rawlsian scholarship has basically been founded on a mistaken assumption. Okay, that's an, oh, and six minutes. Okay, so I have a whole section, how Rawls went wrong. And what I try to do there is try to reconstruct, you know, the particular social group of which Rawls was a member, and you know, the sort of distinctive shortcomings, opacities, blind spots of this group. But because of time, I'm going to skip over this. But I'd recommend to everybody who's interested in these issues, this, you know, very informative book by Katrina Forrester, young woman at Harvard. It's basically a history of ideas book rather than a philosophy book, but it gives this wonderful reconstruction of the particular milieu of, you know, the postwar scene, three crucial institutions, I think Harvard, Princeton, and Oxford, and that's where egalitarian racial liberalism was founded, you know, in the work of those people. And you know, the problem is that it's a very limited group of people, it's not sort of looking outside their circles, and it's not raising questions that other people would have raised. And I just want to sort of point to one of them in particular. The standard narrative, as I say, is that Anglo-American political philosophy was moribund in the '50s and '60s until it was revived by Rawls, and in addition, Rawls made the innovative move of changing the subject, the normative subject of political philosophy, away from our obligation to the state to social justice. I'm going to suggest to you that that is another just so story which is false, and the reason is there's a long African-American political tradition which long predates Rawls, which goes back, you know, to the early Revolutionary period, which is certainly has representatives in the 19th century, whose focus, from the very start, is racial justice. And there's a big book coming out, Melvin - [Audience Member] Rogers. - [Charles Mills] Thanks, yes. Say it, say it - [Audience Member] Rogers. - [Charles Mills] Melvin Rogers, at Brown, political theorist at Brown. And Chip, that's his nickname, sorry, one of those senior moments, anyway, it's coming out (laughs) at green light at University of Chicago Press. So it's going to be this huge book, basically looking, each chapter, a particular African-American political theorist, and my hope is, and certainly the editor's hope is that this will become a sort of, you know, standard text showing, look, there is this sort of long, important African-American tradition, and it needs to be engaged with by mainstream Euro-American political theory. And that's going to include Euro-American political philosophy and Euro-American discussions of justice, because as I say, what comes out completely clearly if you read this book is that social justice has been a theme for the start for these folks, racial justice has been a theme, and these people are Anglo-American, I mean, they're English-speaking, they're citizens of the United States, you know, what could be sort of more appropriately Anglo-American than that? So one of the things that we need to do in terms of, you know, sort of making philosophy more representative is to recognize that there's a long history of discussions of justice, and this very sort of narrow genealogy that mainstream white political philosophy have given us is really utterly misleading. Okay, last section, liberal racial justice. How much time do I have? Could an organizer point and tell me how much time I have? No organizer is willing to do so. There is a danger I will go on and on and on. - [Audience Member] Do it! - [Charles Hall] How much? (Tad Schmaltz speaking off mic) Okay, I'll go for another 10 minutes. Okay, so if I'm right that the Rawlsian literature cannot handle race, not merely contingently, that they have chosen not to do so, but if this epiphany is correct, that it turns out the apparatus is just not designed for it and was never meant by Rawls to be designed for it because it only applies to societies with non-racialized basic structures, within the I zone, so what can one do? My suggestion is that what we do is turn to a different modeling of society and a different contract. And here, surprise, surprise, I'm going to put in a plug for my own earlier work. And there's a well-known political theorist, Carole Pateman, who wrote a book in 1988, The Sexual Contract, and I was inspired by Carole's book to write my first Racial Contract, and we also did a book together, Contract and Domination and in the latter book, Contract and Domination, we had separate chapters because we disagreed on various things, I argued that you could transform the contract model, following her work and following the even earlier work of Jean-Jacques Rousseau in Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, you could use a contract to model domination. So in Rousseau's Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, he basically says contract theory is a scam. Contract theory is a scam insofar as, as he sort of tells the sort of history of society, people in the state of nature, then society, there's an early stage, which is very egalitarian, and then private property develops, divisions between rich and poor sharpen, the wealthy become worried about the threat to their property, so it's if you're into conspiracy theories, as many people in the left are, it's a great example in political philosophy of conspiracy theory. The wealthy get together and say, hey, let's come up with a set of norms and principles that are going to supposedly protect everybody's rights, and everybody will sort of sign up for it, but in reality, plutocracy will be basically embedded behind the scenes. So you can see that I'm suggesting as an early statement of the class contract. So Rousseau, the class contract, Pateman, Sexual Contract, then Mills, Racial Contract. You can see I'm trying to sort of link myself to the great white tradition and thereby make myself respectable. (audience laughing) So anyway, so my argument is that we think a kind of extrapolation of these three, a sort of abstract representation, it's the idea of a domination contract. The domination contract is not inclusive. It's basically for a group of the privileged to sort of recognize themselves as equal and basically see other people as unequal and then structure society and the polity and the economy around that. So I suggest that to do racial justice in a social contract framework, we need to shift from the consensual contract to the domination contract. And the domination contract is not, of course, to be endorsed by us, rather, we need to ask ourselves how do we dismantle it? So in the case of gender, it's a sexual contract. In the case of race, it's a racial contract. So here is my revision of the Rawlsian thought experiment. You are once again behind Rawls's veil of ignorance, but the experiment is set up in a different way. Rawls's principles are principles for an ideal and just society. You're going to be looking for principles for an unjust society. So we're going to say, when the veil lifts, you're going to find yourself in a white supremacist society, and the question you need to ask yourself is what race will I turn out to be? So once again, as with the Rawlsian original, you're using self-interest as a motivator, combining it with ignorance, and out of that combination, we're hoping to get a principled judgment which can stand up by moral criteria. So the idea would be, as a white person, you ask yourself, okay, I'm doing this thought experiment. Suppose the veil lifts, and let's say I'm a black woman in a ghetto in south side Chicago, or let's say I'm a Latina somewhere in the southwestern United States, or I'm a Native American on the reservation. What principles of justice, what particular structure of public policy would I want to see put in place so as to make sure, assure as seriously as I can, that I'm not going to be radically handicapped in this social system? And the idea would be that by carrying out this thought experiment, you then force everybody who's doing it in good faith to sort of have the subject of racial justice center stage rather than offstage altogether, which for the most part it is in the mainstream social justice world. And what I've argued elsewhere is that you would come up with three principles of corrective racial justice. One, end second-class civic status, and historically, people of color have been seen as, you know, second class or even sort of lower. Two, end racial exploitation, and three, end racial disrespect. And I suggest that these principles are not merely what we would choose on prudential grounds behind the veil, but that they comport with our moral intuitions outside the veil, you know, that these are principles that are morally defensible principles, but that these principles that might seem on the face of it to be sort of innocuous, Mom and apple pie, who could disagree, so what, would really have very radical implications, because, for example, ending second-class status would mean, for example, things like revoking the Shelby decision, it would mean, like, dismantling the ghetto, it would mean radical revision of the prison-industrial complex, ending racial exploitation. We'd have to sort of look at the question of what have been the sort of, what have been the processes in terms of mortgage discrimination, in terms of the racial implementation of the GI Bill after World War Two, in terms of discrimination, all those, so a sort of huge set of economic processes, the kinds of things that Coates spoke about in his famous Atlantic article. You can then make a case for reparations on those grounds. And finally, racial disrespect. What I'm talking about here, situation where historically, people of color have not been seen as moral equals, sort of racial contempt has suffused the society, leading to expressive harms. And of course, if we look at the literature, black American, Latin, native literature, this has been a sort of constant theme. We're not seen as equal human beings. So what you then need to do is what would you have to do in terms of, you know, public expressions of respect to sort of, you know, take account of that past. So there are things we've seen already in terms of, you know, Civil War statuary and monuments, using Native Americans as mascots, rewritings of textbooks to sort of, you know, talk about the contributions of people of color, but it would mean a sort of global reconstitution of the United States, and you know, it would seem like a very radical one, and maybe even seem like a non-liberal one, but final point I want to drive home is it's non-liberal by the standards of a liberalism that has been racialized. And what I've tried to make a case for is that for a liberalism that takes a history of racial subordination seriously, it is not non-liberal at all. So for anybody in this room who thinks of themselves as a good liberal, whether a good liberal on the left or on the right, my claim is, outrageous as it may seem, you should be completely on board with this program. Thank you. (audience applauding) You mean I said nothing controversial? - [Tad Schmaltz] I'll just, so we do have some time for questions. Thank you. I think we have people with a microphone. Is that working? Yes, there it is. Okay, yes. (audience member speaking off mic) There's the microphone there. - [Audience Member] My name's Ian Fishback. When I was a child, we had Niemoller's poem in the dining room, as a child, Niemoller's poem, first they came for the communists, then they came for the, and I think maybe that's what you're shooting for in your idea of a veil of ignorance. - [Charles Mills] Well, it's really Rawls's (Mills speaking off mic) - [Audience Member] When Rawls, I was somewhat mystified by the fact that you didn't treat Rawls's discussion of conscientious objection and civil disobedience, because I think that speaks to a lot of the issues you're talking about, but that's a separate issue. My concern has more, is more specific to Ann Arbor. So Ann Arbor is reverse racist and reverse sexist. And this is common now in many societies. And what happens is it drives white men to the right. I'm in a situation now politically where I can literally choose between a president who is actually racist and sexist, that I hate, and a society here that has violated my rights in ways that are absolutely unconscionable. I am leaving the United States. I will not be back. (audience members applauding) Goodbye. - [Audience Member] Goodbye. - [Charles Mills] Okay. - [Audience Member] You don't know what I've done for this country. You disgust me. - [Charles Mills] What I'd want to say is (audience member speaking off mic) - [Tad Schmaltz] Oh, please. - [Charles Mills] What I'd want to say is that I'm - [Audience Member] How can you not stick up for me? (audience member speaking off mic) - [Organizer] Because he's answering the, he's - [Charles Mills] What I'd want to say to you, sir, is that I'm sorry you had that reaction, and - [Audience Member] Sorry is not enough. Stand up for me. - [Charles Mills] Well, what I want to stand up for is a just (audience member speaking off mic) a just society, and in a just society, but you see, the fact (audience member speaking off mic) but the fact that you're leaving suggests a lack of good faith. So you asked a question. I'm trying to answer it. - [Audience Member] You know that this is bad faith. She knows that this is bad faith. There are other people in this audience that know that you are acting worse than Nazis. It's disgusting. - [Audience Member] What? Get out. - [Audience Member] You can laugh if you want, but it's true. There are people here who know it. - [Audience Member] What? - [Audience Member] Get out. - [Audience Members] Get out. (audience murmuring) - [Charles Mills] Okay, well, I suspect that maybe the question was not in good faith, so let's have one that is. - [Tad Schmaltz] Yes, other questions, please. - [Audience Member] Yes, I have other questions. (audience laughing) Hello. Dr. Mills, my name is Asya Harrison. - [Charles Mills] Oh, yes, sorry. - [Audience Member] I'm a doctoral student here in education and psychology. And one of the, you made such amazing points throughout your entire talk. Thank you so much for being here today. And I wonder, as an educator, you speak about how there's little representation, right, so you are in these philosopher spaces, and you are hearing where all of these ideas and these conceptualizations are being formed, and you're looking around, and you're seeing, like, a predominantly white room. So as an educator, like, in front of undergrads, like, with a mission of wanting to put people of color, like, in these spaces so that voices are heard, how would you recommend that we get people into this area, especially when we think about the ways that a lot of college courses are, you know, like, filtering and used as, like, gate-keeping, you know what I mean? - [Charles Mills] Okay, I thought there had been (audience members applauding) a self-conscious effort, especially given that it's February and Black History Month, to sort of reach out to the African-American community on campus since this is an issue of obvious concern to them. To the specific dynamics of Michigan, I obviously can't speak to that. In terms of the sort of general things I would recommend, what I've been doing for some time, I argue that philosophers should try to incorporate such material into their courses in general. I mean, it's okay to have a critical theory of race course or a critical philosophy of race course or a DuBois course, which in fact I've taught at CUNY, but the danger is that those courses are then seen as not real philosophy. So real philosophy is the sort of, you know, usual crowd, you know Hume, Locke, Hobbes, Liebniz and so forth, and then if you have these weird special interests, you could do a course like that. So it then means you get to avoid such material if you don't have any particular interest in it in the first place, whereas a more appropriate strategy, in my opinion, would be both to have such courses, but to incorporate material of race into mainstream courses. So philosophy of history courses can look at competing views of history, the views, for example, you find in people like DuBois. Philosophy of science courses could write the history of scientific racism and what that says, what the social influence on your scientific research, metaphysics courses, there's a lot of material now on the metaphysics of race, work by Professor Anderson's friend and my friend Sally Haslanger, so there's all epistemology courses, huge amount of stuff now on social epistemology, a significant part of it which involves issues of race. So I think that part of what we need to do in all disciplines, but speaking for philosophy, see how race can be incorporated into the curriculum so that even what we think of as mainstream courses have race in it, because it's not as if you are distorting the material by doing so, because race does in fact permeate the social order. As I say, historically, and you could disagree about whether it's still currently, but historically, the US has been a white supremacist state. I mean, this is, you know, there is massive documentation on this. So this has influenced all kinds of things. It influences psychology, it influences sense of identity. So philosophy should be able to sort of take on these issues, and then in political theory similarly. I know people, as I mentioned, there are texts I mentioned whose authors, whose editors, embarrassingly, I couldn't recall, they're both political theorists. They're trying to transform political theory. International relations, there's a new strain, critical IR theorists, and again, their thought of looking at the extent to which, you know, basically from the age of imperialism onwards, race has been tied up with international relations, because of course, the presumption has been, as Europeans, we get to conquer you other nations. International law was largely sort of written in racialized ways. So there's all kinds of stuff. I mean, race is not siloed. Race is not cabined. Race permeated the social order so that the disciplines that study the socio-political order, you know, there ought to be material in race in all of them. - [Audience Member] Thank you. - [Tad Schmaltz] Other questions? Yes. - [Audience Member] Thank you. Stephen Modell, School of Public Health. I'm interested in the solutions you are proposing towards the end, in particular, granting greater respect to an individual or a group. That would seem to have certain principles behind it, but it's rather elusive. In the context of dialogue, it might mean making sure that you entitle a person with adequate respect, like Doctor, or beginning to put yourself in their frame of mind, in their shoes. But I think that maybe you mean something more. Could you explain? - [Charles Mills] Okay, if you mean the veil of if you mean the veil of ignorance thought experiment, yes, that's the idea, that you imagine yourself behind this veil, and as I say, you're considering the possibility that when the veil lifts, because the veil is supposed to conceal from you your identity, so that when the veil lifts, let us say you find you're a citizen of a white supremacist state, and you're not white, you're a person of color, so that there's a whole history of people of color and how they are disadvantaged by this physically, psychologically, how it's affected them all kinds of ways, and you ask yourself, if I were a person of color, what would I want to see the government doing in terms of public policy to change this situation so that I could basically feel myself to be an equal in this society rather than somebody who's inferior. So it's asking the people who have been privileged historically in the US and in many other countries also to imagine themselves as people of color, and on that basis, to choose principles of justice. So it wouldn't require an effort Susan Moller Okin, you know, a book from three three, is it three or is it more, many decades ago, Justice, Gender, and the Family imagined something similar for gender, and she did point out that one problem was the difficulty men would have in putting themselves in women's shoes. And you could see, in terms of in a if you think of the hearings on Kavanaugh, for example, you could see that this problem is still alive and well. So what would a man, in good faith trying to do the experiment have to do? Well, you know, you read feminist texts, you read feminist fiction, you sort of, you know, open your ears to the kind of witnessing that women have done so that you sort of get an appreciation what is it like to be a woman in a patriarchal society. So I am suggesting a comparable move in terms of race, except unlike Okin, I'm sort of making it explicitly. I'm saying the veil is going to lift, and you're in a racist white supremacist society, not an ideal society. Corrective justice is going to be your priority. What measures of corrective justice would you want to make sure that are put in place so that you're not disadvantaged in your new identity as a person of color. - [Audience Member] Thank you very much. - [Tad Schamltz] Yes, please. - [Audience Member] Hi, my name's Eugenia. I'm a doctoral student in the department of political science, and I mostly study political socialization, and in particular, empathy. And I was wondering, with this veil of ignorance thought experiment you're talking about, how we could perhaps, if it's the case that white supremacy and white supremacist states permeate into psychology, right, if you're 18, 20 years old and you're in a philosophy class, and this is where you're starting the veil of ignorance experiment, or thought experiment, you're constrained, right. You might have really a hard time imagining and thinking of this example of stepping into another person's shoes. So in my work, I try to, like, think about developmental steps and education in particular. So I was wondering how we could perhaps adapt these ideas to elementary school or middle school curriculums, right, where you're learning about things from an objective perspective that assumes white supremacy, right, so like, how do, what are your thoughts about transferring these ideas to youth-oriented or child-oriented programs? - [Charles Mills] Well, part of what I would argue is that the third principle, which is ending racial disrespect, is going to require, and this is a problem, of course, because it sounds so radical when you say it. It's going to require a national effort at the educational level, starting much earlier than university, which I take it is the point you're making, insofar as racialized cognition begins at a very early stage. So the kind of stuff that's studied under the categories of implicit bias and so forth and, you know, the controlling images that, say, Patricia Hill Collins wrote about in terms of black women, all those things, you know, massively documented in social science literature and social psychology literature, those kinds of things need to be taken on board by mainstream political philosophers because what it means is that you're getting you're basically getting a situation where your cognition is being shaped to disrespect people in certain categories from the time you're a kid, from the time you're a child, so that you would then need to ask yourself, what kind of re-education or, re-education has ominous (chuckles) implications given the sort of history, obviously, of socialist governments. What kind of program of education would be called for so that you grow up with a sort of basic respect for your fellow citizens, so respect is a default mode rather than a situation where, for people of color, it's often disrespect that's a default mode? So that's going to require a massive program involving people with expertise in all kinds of areas. And as I say, the problem is that it will seem to many people, this is a violation of liberal principles, a violation of, you know, freedom of speech and so forth. But if it's the case that you think that we should all be committed to respecting, you know, other people as, you know, equal citizens in public forums, then the problem is that the idea of separating, so you have your racist views, you would keep them private, and in public, you know, you respect people, it's going to be very hard to make that distinction because it means you're socialized as a person and a significant amount of this stuff is unconscious, so it's not the case that you have a sort of easy way of sort of pulling a lever, okay, I'm now in the public sphere, so I'm now going to sort of act in a non-racist way. So we can see what kind of response of hostility there would be to such programs. But in a society where historically, implicit bias and racialized and gender perceptions, you know, the objectification of women, I mean, you could easily run this out in terms of the objectification of women, failing to see women as equal persons, so they're focused on race here. In the paper itself, I mention briefly that I'm abstracting race out for an analytic exercise, but in reality, it's a multi-dimensional system of domination, and as I'm sure you know, for decades, if not in philosophy, there's literature on intersectionality, the question of how these sort of connections play themselves out for different identities, so all of those complications would have to be taken into account. But yes, I think, you know, that seemingly very simple principle, correcting, ending racial disrespect, ending disrespect for women, that would really require all kinds of interventions, starting at a very early stage. - [Tad Schmaltz] Thank you. We have a question right here. Is there someone in the area with a microphone? - [Audience Member] Should I ask mine, or? - [Tad Schamltz] Oh, okay, go ahead, and then we'll get to you. - [Audience Member] My name is Trevor Bechtel. I'm staff at a research initiative here at the university that focuses on poverty in a social science perspective. Last night, in a course on ethics and poverty, I talked about Rawls and how it's reframed by Sen and Nussbaum to think about capability deprivation in terms of poverty, and so if the kind of root of that is kind of trashed by your really eloquent talk, which I think you've done a good job of, I'm wondering what ways we need to kind of rethink some of that other work. So are there ways in which this kind of stuff on race can also apply to poverty, either in the kind of sense in which race and poverty are deeply connected or in the ways in which they can be teased apart? - [Charles Mills] Okay, well, to give him credit, and I focus on the critique, but one needs to be fair, there are many people who would say that if you have a social democratic view on things, the best 20th century statement of the social democratic vision is John Rawls's A Theory of Justice. So I've been critical of Rawls for the problem of race, but you know, the social democratic statement that he gives, arguably, you know, the sort of most impressive philosophical rationale for social democratic vision is in that book. There are people who consider themselves (speaking indistinctly) left of Rawls, Brian Barry, a well-known British guy, died some years ago, he was critical of Rawls, though simply there are a lot of things Rawls was saying, from the left, you know, you could make critiques from the left and say that behind the veil, you would argue for more radical changes than Rawls does. There's a book that came out many years ago in the sort of dying phase of what was then called analytical Marxism, a guy called Rodney Peffer, a book way back in 1990. So he uses a Rawlsian apparatus and says that behind the veil, if you know how capitalism works, you would basically argue for principles more radical than Rawls's own principles. But what I'd want to say is that there's already, within philosophy and political theory, more in philosophy, maybe, a well-developed body of work on egalitarianism, social democracy, and so forth, and Rawls's book, though I've been critical of it, is a very important contribution to that field. So I wanted to focus on race because race is not co-incident with class, racial oppression has dimensions of its own, but I would not want to leave the impression that Rawls does not have a very useful set of things to say that, if implemented, if implemented, I mean, obviously, the complication is you know, what I'm claiming is that in sort of in a trumping has become an unfortunate term. Trumping is widely used as a verb in philosophy, like this trumps that. Can we use trump anymore? Anyway, the trumping of class issues by race in terms of people's psychology and so forth would basically be a problem. But the social democratic vision in Rawls is a very attractive one, and I would not want to give the impression that it's not. It couldn't be implemented as is because the point is the causal roots leading to racial disadvantage are, in crucial respects, different from the class roots. It's not just a sort of class and black working class and white. I mean, so, and things I mentioned earlier, like, you know, the racist implementation of the GI Bill, mortgage discrimination, original discrimination against, you know, people of color who wanted to enter trade unions largely controlled by whites, there's a whole set of causes which make race different. But insofar as there's a class vision in Rawls of how to basically reduce class difference and you know, make a situation where class is more sort of fluid in the sense that you're born in a particular social stratum, but you have the possibility of moving up, it is a radical vision that's actually far to the left of what is in the United States now. - [Tad Schamltz] Okay, just, so I have we have 10 minutes at most and three questions left. So here, here, and here. Please. - [Audience Member] Thank you for the very stimulating talk. I'm wondering, if I'm not completely misunderstanding you, that essentially, what you find so, I guess, attractive about Rawls, other than being you cannot hear? (audience member speaking off mic) Sure. (audience member speaking off mic) Okay, I'll try. So I'm wondering if what you find attractive about Rawls, other than being located in philosophy, is the sort of the rigor of the Rawlsian method and the veil of ignorance, and so if that's the case, then if you would embrace, I guess, a description of your sort of project, at least as portrayed in the latter part of your talk today, as a form of sort of like imminent critique, right, where essentially, you are accepting certain principles that he's advancing, and then you're trying to see really where that gets you if you're upholding a standard of rigor that exceeds even Rawls's. And so if you would sort of agree with that characterization of part of what you've done in today's talk, if you have anything additional to say as far as what that gets you in terms of an intellectual project or a vision that would transcend the Rawlsian project, because interestingly, you couch your endpoint as sort of racial liberalism, right, and so in some sense you want to use the method not to transcend Rawls, but in some sense, to, and I'm searching here for the nature of the, of what it is you would like to do to the Rawlsian, I guess, theoretical tradition. Hope that makes sense. - [Charles Mills] Okay, what I'm calling racial liberal is not what I'm advocating, I'm diagnosing as a problem. So I'm saying liberalism has been racialized, so let's call it racialized liberalism, racial liberalism, and then my project is how do we deracialize it. It's Rawlsian insofar as I'm using the device of the veil of ignorance and focus on the basic structure. But insofar as I'm saying that we used a domination contract rather than a consensual contract, you could say it's not really imminent in that sense because the domination contract is locating itself on theoretical terrain that's very different, obviously. So I would say there are elements from Rawls, absolutely, but there are also elements that are quite opposed to the way Rawls frames things. As I say, his starting point is, in the opening pages of A Theory of Justice, we're going to consider society as a cooperative venture of mutual advantage with reciprocally beneficial rules, and only a tiny subset, well, okay, if you think of the length of time hunter-gatherer societies lasted, maybe it's, you know, tens of thousands of years, so maybe in terms of time, it's a fairly large amount, but certainly once you sort of exit that stage, you don't find societies that conform to that structure. So I am then saying we need to make a fundamental break and recognize that insofar as social contract theory is tied to this way of modeling society, it's fundamentally flawed. So in that respect, my critique is clearly not imminent, but external. - [Tad Schmaltz] Yes. - [Audience Member] Okay, this is on. Thanks for your talk, and sorry, over here. - [Charles Mills] There you are, yes, sir. - [Audience Member] Sorry that you had to deal with the heckling. - [Charles Mills] No problem. - [Audience Member] Yeah, so my question is, like, let's take for granted that, like, the right-wing alternatives to liberalism are pretty ugly and, you know, we gotta do whatever we can to stop them. Why defend liberalism from, you know, whatever left-wing alternatives it currently has, like, I don't know, socialism, anarchism, what have you? - [Charles Mills] Yes, sure. It's a question that I've been asked many times (coughs) sorry, in such presentations. And what I would say is that insofar as you're trying to win people over to a political project, then it seems to me you're likely to be more successful if you start where their heads already are. So as I say, liberalism, this is uncontroversial, liberalism has been the dominant political ideology in United States history. There's been a lot of work on this, though of course there's a question of whether you have strains that are antithetical to it. So there's well-known political theorists out there, at Penn, Rogers Smith, recent president of the APSA. He says there are multiple traditions in the US, so there's a liberal tradition, but it's in competition with others, and then my claim has been what is sometimes identified as the thesis of, as a kind of symbiosis, that liberalism has been symbiotic with racism and sexism and so forth. Nonetheless, in this expanded sense that includes left and right, I think most Americans regard themselves as liberals. So if you can say to people, if you're a good liberal, you should be on board with a racial justice program, or for that matter, a gender justice program or a class justice program, that seems to me to be an immense ideological advantage, whereas if you say to people, have I got a great ideology for you, it's a non-liberal ideology, but hear me out, then you're facing a kind of barrier just to start with. So certainly, you can do a critique from further left. You can try to revive a Marxist vision. But part of the problem is going to be that you're going to have to say to people, okay, the 20th century history of states calling themselves Marxist was disastrous, nonetheless, we're going to try again, and here I have this model for how a Marxist economy could work. And part of the problem with that is that the theorization of post-capitalist economies, a modern industrial economy that's post-capitalist, we don't have any plausible models for it yet. So what I want to say is we could consider it an open question, but at the present, in the absence of such a model, at the very least, it's going to be difficult to convince people of stuff. As I'm sure everybody in the room knows, Sanders, I am warning New Hampshire, and the question that is immediately raised for a lot of commentators, okay, so he's got this far, maybe he could even go all the way, but anybody who is running under the rubric of democratic socialism in the United States is going to face a firestorm which is going to be aimed in part, from a mixed metaphor here, in linking him with socialism of other kinds, non-democratic socialism. So if Bernie Sanders is going to sort of face that kind of critique, what kind of response do you think you're going to get from a position that starts off from the left of Sanders in the first place? So I am saying this is a program that even people on the political right should get on board with insofar as racial justice, racial injustice is supposed to violate basic norms that even right-wing liberals should be able to agree with, I mean, you know, life, liberty, and property, these are seen as sort of classic rights that the political right would endorse, as against things like, you know, right to health care and so forth. Well, you know, the experience of indigenous expropriation, experience of chattel slavery, the experience of post-emancipation discrimination, in theory, people on the political right should see these operators also. In reality, unfortunately, they don't. Robert Nozick, well-known libertarian theorist, still the philosophical classic Anarchy, State, and Utopia, he has a brief discussion of corrective justice for the history of slavery, but later libertarians have not followed up on this. But at least in principle, everybody on the liberal spectrum should be able to see that racial injustice is wrong and that we should all get together and support a project of racial justice. - [Tad Schmaltz] So this is our last question here. - [Audience Member] Thank you. Thank you very much for your time, Professor. My question is, is what is the role of racial justice in furthering (speaking indistinctly) debate on principles of redistribution? What role do you see for racial justice in furthering that specific academic debate? - [Charles Mills] The aim would be to bring into the social justice literature, which, as I say, has been thriving for the past half-century since Rawls's work, an issue which to me is very important and I think objectively should be seen as very important that is hardly discussed at all. And here is an example which might be useful for you. In the past 15 years, there have been a lot of companions to Rawls, introductions to Rawls, guidebooks to Rawls. There's a big one, I think it might be the handbook, that came out about five years ago. And this handbook of nearly 600 pages has a grand total of about one and a half pages on race, and if we look in the index for affirmative action, which is arguably the most important measure of corrective justice in the United States in the postwar period, you will get, if you look in the index, you will get a reference to a single sentence. So there's a single sentence in this book on affirmative action. So that, to me, is a manifestation of the utter marginalization of race. And it's not merely on the left-liberal side of the spectrum, it's on the right-wing side among libertarians, people who are not in the liberal philosophical community, people who think of themselves as communitarian theorists. It's basically across the board. And as I've said in the paper and I will say again, though, you know, some people disagree, the whiteness of the profession is, for me, a major contributory factor. It does not surprise us that it's only when women begin to enter the profession in significant numbers in the 1970s, it's not, it's only then you begin to get a sort of systematic treatment of gender and gender injustice. Likewise, it should not surprise us that in a 97 percent white profession, there has been little interest and concern about, you know, sort of exploring the question of racial justice. So I'm trying to sort of change the discourse. I'm trying to sort of ask white political philosophers, if you're serious about social justice and if Rawls himself says, as he did, that matters of non-ideal theory are the really important ones, where is the literature on corrective racial justice? - [Tad Schmaltz] So before we thank our speaker, I'd like to remind you that there will be a symposium tomorrow. YOu're all welcome and encouraged to attend that. It starts at 10 a.m. on the fourth flour of the amphitheater and hope to see many of you there. Let's thank our speaker for a very stimulating talk. - [Charles Mills] Thank you. - [Organizer] Thank you. (audience applauding) - [Charles Mills] Thank you for coming and staying.
Info
Channel: University of Michigan
Views: 14,050
Rating: 4.7462687 out of 5
Keywords:
Id: 78wzAfQu9Mw
Channel Id: undefined
Length: 118min 51sec (7131 seconds)
Published: Mon Feb 17 2020
Related Videos
Note
Please note that this website is currently a work in progress! Lots of interesting data and statistics to come.