Professor Donald
Kagan: Peisistratus died in 527 with all his power,
insofar as we know peacefully, and was succeeded in the
tyranny over Athens by his sons, by first wife,
Hippeis who was the elder and Hipparchus.
I think it's proper to think of Hippeis as the man in charge,
but Hipparchus shared considerable amount of his power
and responsibility. At first it appears that they
ruled in the same way that their father had, which was to say one
that was moderate and didn't cause a great deal of opposition
in Athens, and, of course,
there always was a certain amount of opposition.
We should not forger that. Aristocratic families always
vying for their own power and their own position were
uncomfortable very often under Peisistratus and different ones,
different families got into trouble and were driven out,
and our old friends the Alcmaeonidae got into trouble
again, were banished in the time of
the sons of Peisistratus, and it was necessary to have a
battle against them, in which they were defeated and
driven out. That will play a
significant role in the future of Athens quite soon.
But I think it's in the year 514 that a very important event
changes the course of things. There is a personal quarrel
between the tyrants, one of the tyrants actually,
and one of the noble young men, which results in a plot to kill
both Hippeis and Hipparchus, led by two young men who will
become known in Athenian lore as the tyrannicides,
because in their plot they succeed in killing the younger
brother Hipparchus, although they don't get Hippeis.
They themselves are killed and the plot fails,
but its significance, I think,
comes in the fact that it made Hippeis thereafter very nervous,
very concerned about his safety and about the future of his
regime, and the nature of the regime
according to tradition changes and it becomes very harsh,
and there are persecutions of people, who are suspected of
perhaps plotting or hoping to plot against the tyranny,
and that's significant. It's a characteristic
event, as I told you early on as I spoke about tyranny in
general; usually in the second and
sometimes if they made it to the third, there would be
opposition. The opposition would make the
rulers nervous, the nervous rulers would then
misbehave and create further opposition and that's the story
as it happens in Athens. One wrinkle in the Athenian
story is that the Alcmaeonidae, who had been expelled from the
city, always active,
always thinking, got into a position of a
special favor to the Delphic Oracle,
when there was an earthquake that badly damaged the temple of
Apollo at Delphi. The Alcmaeonidae bid for the
contract to rebuild the temple, and in the doing of that,
they spent some of their own money to make the temple even
more beautiful than the contract required,
which put them in great favor with the priests of Delphi,
and they immediately cashed this favor in,
in the form of seeking their own political advantage.The
story, as Herodotus tells it, is that their goal was to drive
out Hippeis from Athens and the way to do it this time--you
remember they've tried every trick in the world,
and it hasn't really worked. The idea now was to turn to the
most powerful military state in Greece and use it for their
purposes. I'm talking of course about
Sparta. The tale is that whenever the
Spartans sent a message to the Delphic Oracle asking for the
opportunity to consult the Oracle,
the answer that came back was: first free the Athenians.
Well, whether that was the reason or he had reasons of his
own, the very ambitious King of Sparta,
King Cleomenes was to undertake the job of removing Hippeis from
power in Athens quite soon. It's in the year 511-10 that
the Spartans under Cleomenes will invade Attica,
gain control of the state, and remove Hippeis and
withdraw. But I'll come back to that
story in just a moment. Let me conclude our
consideration of the Athenian tyranny by looking at what were
the achievements and consequences of the years of
tyrannical rule--many positive elements,
as was so often the case with tyranny.
From the economic side this was a period of great expansion of
Athenian commerce, trade, very strong to the east
through the Hellespont and to the Black Sea,
but also in this period Athens trades very strongly with the
West. I mean to say chiefly Sicily
and Italy, and in fact up to that point, up to those years
roughly speaking, Corinthian pottery,
fine Corinthian pottery, is dominant in the western
areas and this is no surprise. That's always been the case for
Corinth. But by the end of the sixth
century, Athenian pottery has actually outstripped it in the
western markets, which show you how much this
combination of trade and industry was changing the
character of Athens and making it wealthier and bringing along
various elements of change in their way of life.
Another consequence of the tyrannical experience in Athens
was a diminution in the power of the aristocracy,
and this again is the general story wherever we see tyranny in
the Greek world. It never erases aristocracy;
you never see the disappearance of the distinction between
nobles and commoners, and claims to the aristocracy
of birth and descent from the gods.
It is always there. Even in the most democratic of
Greeks states, like Athens for instance,
aristocracy doesn't go away. It's not abolished;
it lives side by side with a democratic constitution.
But the domination by the aristocracy, the monopoly of all
the powers and influence that they used to have,
it's not there and that is a tremendously important
consequence. So, when the tyranny goes away
and it's necessary to reconstruct a new Athenian
constitution, the answer will not simply be
to return to the old days before the tyrants.
Solon had intervened in an important way and the tyrants
had made their contribution too, to changes that turned out to
be permanent. It's also true that under the
tyrants, the local power of the noblemen had been reduced and
the power of the government in Athens,
which was not dominated by the aristocracy, but by the
tyrants--that was a trend and one of the issues that would
have to be worked out would be what would be the relationship
between the localities outside of Athens and the city itself.
Localism has been damaged but not abolished.
If there are going to be new forms of government that
take place, one of the consequences,
one of the precursors of that will be to further strengthen
the center and weaken the periphery,
and to continue to strip as best one could the influence and
power of the aristocracy, which was mainly to be felt in
the countryside and to increase the power of some other form of
government, which center would be in Athens.
On the other hand, because of the reforms of
Solon, which I remind you Peisistratus and his sons
allowed to stay in place, at least in the formal
sense--therefore every year, think about it,
people were elected archon,
people where chosen for a council, law courts operated,
all of these things not dominated by the aristocracy,
but really, in the case of the magistracies,
wealth was the criterion. Remember ever since Solon
that people who were not aristocrats, but were wealthy
also participated in those jobs, and the council which was open
to three out of the four Athenian classes under Solon,
meant that people actually went to the council chamber,
participated in decisions about what was going on.
To be sure they weren't going to do anything that the tyrants
didn't want, but ninety to ninety five percent of the time,
maybe more, the tyrant didn't care, so that they were
getting--this is the point I really want to stress.
They were getting experience in the business of self government.
When you do that, I think the history of the
world shows that once people have risen to that state,
where they do participate in their own self government,
it's very hard to get them back into a state when they don't
anymore. That's going to be very
difficult to make stick. Athens has been moved down
the road to self government as a consequence, strangely enough,
of the tyranny. Just in passing,
I might point out that's not a unique phenomenon.
It's very interesting to look back at the early post-colonial
age in the twentieth century and to see that there were real
differences between colonies that had been ruled in a--I
don't want to say tyrannical, but in an absolute way,
such as the Congo or other places like that,
as opposed to places that had achieved some degree of self
government, even while they were ruled by
European power, the difference was very great.
The same experience that I am talking about now that lead to
the capacity and a determination to govern oneself was more
likely in places where there had been some such thing.
India, of course, is a striking example.
Where the Indians had managed to achieve some degree of
participation in the government of their own state under the
British, who in spite of all the
troubles they had, have actually produced a
functioning relatively democratic government in that
great subcontinent. Well, that's the sort of thing
I'm talking about. So, knowing what we now
know, looking backward, it's possible to say that it
looks like the tyranny played a very important role in the
transition from aristocratic government to democracy.
That's not what the tyrants intended.
They intended to rule for as long as they could,
but it was one of the consequences as we will see.
Well, let's turn once again to those Alcmaeonidae who had,
as you remember a checkered past in Athens and even under
the tyranny, because they had been driven
out. Remember Megacles had his deal
with Peisistratus, and how Peisistratus had broken
that deal, so he went into opposition.
He and the Alcmaeonidae were driven out, but they came back,
because we find Cleisthenes name on the list of archons,
but then they had been driven out again.
In the year 511-10, Cleisthenes who was leader of
the Alcmaeonidae family, and political faction was in
exile and was working to get the Spartans to do the job that was
done. So Cleomenes takes his Spartan
army in 510, he drives out the tyrants, and then he goes home.
Now, the question that confronts the Athenians is what
form of government should we have?
Again, there's a whole range of possibilities.
Not a whole range, there are a few possibilities.
One would be reactionary. Let's go back to the days
before Solon when the aristocracy was everything.
There's certainly, as we will see where people who
wanted to do something very much like that.
On the other hand, what are you going to do about
all these people of consequence who are wealthy and who have
made it to the top, but who were not aristocrats?
Then what are you going to do about all of these family
farmers of whom there must be more now than ever because of my
suggestion that Peisistratus had taken away land from some exiled
aristocrats and distributed among families,
some of whom were successful on farms and became hoplite
soldiers and independent farmers.
They're not going to enjoy being put back to a position
which was worse than they had under the tyranny.
Because under the tyranny they were sitting on councils,
and participating in these things,
sitting in courts and now all this was going to be taken away,
if the reactionary aristocracy had its way.
That was really what the contest was, I think.
Should we continue with the Solonian Constitution only
without tyrants or should we go back to an aristocracy?
The contest for how to decide that was done in the usual old
fashioned way. That is to say,
in the contest for the archonship.
The candidates of holding one view ran against candidates
holding the other view and that's where the matter would be
decided. But they went at it in the old
way that is the decisions were being made in the political
clubs that belonged to the aristocracy.
In other words, how we're going to do this was
being fought out among the aristocrats, not among the
public at large. In that contest Cleisthenes who
stood for the more moderate, for the Solonian,
let us say, approach as his family had always done,
lost. The winner was a man called
Isagoras, an aristocrat. They were all aristocrats,
of course, and he engages--I should say that this election
takes place after preliminary pushing back and forth in the
year 508-7 and his victory means a victory for the reactionary
program. One of his first actions is to
establish still another council, not the council of four hundred
that Solon had established, but a new council of three
hundred, and it was only made up only of aristocrats.
Second, very interesting and it turns out to be a very important
change--introduced by Isagoras was to scrutinize the citizen's
lists and then to remove from that list lots and lots of
people who were deemed to be, I guess those who were
illegally enrolled in the citizen list.
They were now going to impose retroactively the
traditional criterion for Athenian citizenship.
Is your father an Athenian citizen?
But we know that Solon had already broken through that by
permitting people to come to Athens and to acquire
citizenship, if they had the necessary
skills and there surely had been a fair number of those,
and we are told, that the Peisistratids had done
the same thing for pretty much the same reason.
So, over a couple of generations you had foreigners
coming to Athens and acquiring Athenian citizenship and
undoubtedly using it, who are now going to be
disenfranchised and driven from the citizen lists.
Now, that made for quite a few discontented people in
Athens. If you picked a moment after
which Isagoras has accomplished these two things,
that is establishing the council of 300,
which is obviously going to be the governing body in Athens,
an aristocratic council, and driven "X" number of people
from the citizen lists, then all of those people are
going to be very unhappy, and very likely they have
friends who are also going to be unhappy.
So, you have a situation which is by now means calm and
settled, but it might have settled down as people,
as they usually do when things are unavoidable,
when there is no real option. Nobody's making a different
case; they would have just gotten
used to things, I suppose.
But now Cleisthenes decides to do things different.
He does not accept his defeat as he would have had to do in
the old days, having been defeated in the
aristocratic contest. Instead,
in the words of Herodotus, prohetaerizetai ton
demon, he brought the people into his political faction.
The root of that first word, prosetaerizetai,
is hetaera, which means a club, a political club,
a collection of companions. That's the name for these
aristocratic societies and Cleisthenes broke the rules.
He went out there beyond the aristocratic circle and he
recruited people. You become part of my political
faction. Well, why should they?
Because he had a program that was contrary to the one pursued
by Isagoras. It's one that will result,
when it is successful in the establishment of what everybody
pretty much agrees was the first Athenian democracy.
The reforms that he proposed then--we have to
imagine he actually went around and electioneered.
That was not done before that, and persuaded people to support
him in his programs, and then he put his programs
through. Well, where did he put these
programs through? He surely couldn't have done
that in a council of 300; it would never have passed,
and I'm sure he didn't try. Instead, he acted,
I think, as though there was no council of three hundred.
He did what you would have done, if you wanted to propose a
bill prior to that. You would go to the assembly,
whichwas the Solonian assembly, which had the right to pass
laws. No doubt, it only passed laws
that the Peisistratids wanted, but it was not something new.
It was something people were accustomed to and he went to the
assembly, and he proposed his laws and they were passed.
Well, Isagoras still had the whip hand and he wasn't
going to sit still, while that took place,
and so using the force at his disposal he drove,
which was that of King Cleomenes and the Spartans,
who came back again when called back.
No doubt, what Cleomenes had in mind when he did what he had
done originally, that is, driving out the
Peisistratids, was the establishment of an
aristocratic republic in Athens with his friends being in
charge. That's what the Spartans
typically would do if they could.
So, he was shocked and annoyed, I'm certain,
when he hears his friends have been somehow pushed out of power
and some new fangled kind of a government that lets ordinary
people participate has been instituted.
So, Cleomenes comes back with his forces and drives
Cleisthenes, and we are told--this is interesting figure
and I can't promise that it's right,
but it does show up in Herodotus.
Cleisthenes and seven hundred families, who must have been in
his faction, are driven out of Attica.
But the people are not ready to take that;
they resist, and they have numbers on their
side, and they end up shutting up Cleomenes and his forces,
which are not many. We're talking about probably
hundreds of soldiers, no more than that,
and we must imagine that there are thousands of Athenians out
there who are discontent, and so they shut Cleomenes up
on the Acropolis where he had run for safety with Isagoras at
his side, and finally they cut a deal and
they go home. And Cleisthenes and his
supporters, whom I think it fair to start calling democrats,
have taken over the city by this coup and are ready to go
forward. Now, this requires that
they establish a new constitution,
because they're going to have a regime the like of which no one
had ever seen before. But in trying to understand
this constitution and it's not easy--the ancient sources tell
us a lot about it, but it's not perfectly clear
what's in everybody's mind as they do what they do.
Motives and purposes are not clear as you'll see in a moment.
But anyway, what I want you to fix on is this.
Don't imagine that what's taking place here is even
anything like the American Constitutional Convention in
Philadelphia, where a bunch of delegates have
been selected from here and there, and they all sit and
argue with each other over the hot summer and finally come up
with various plans. It's better,
I think, to think, if we're using historical
analogies to help us, as of course there is nothing
better than that to help us. Think of the French Revolution,
think of the convention where the sort of the mass of the
people have gained control of the situation,
after driving the king from his throne, and after really putting
aside a more aristocratic council that came before it,
and they sit down with radical people running around,
ready to kill people. This is the outfit that's going
to end up killing the king and his queen, and all the
aristocrats they're going to lay their hands on.
In other words, we are in a revolutionary
situation, and there is force and terror are in the air,
and everybody is fully aware of the danger of this,
that, and the other thing, and of some dangers that
probably don't even exist. We are in a situation that
resembles civil war, that could be on the brink of a
serious civil war, and added to that--in other
words, the Athenians, who will be sitting in the
assembly passing the laws that produce the constitution that
Cleisthenes favors, are first of all already afraid
that the local aristocrats will use force or guile against them.
But on top of that there's been two Spartan invasions of Attica
in the last couple of years and there's nothing to stop King
Cleomenes from coming back again,
because he doesn't like the way he's been treated.
In fact, I'd go further; I'd say there's every reason to
fear that that's going to happen.
Again, that's where the analogy to the French Revolution works
again, because nothing that happens in that most radical
period of the French Revolution is understandable.
If you don't know that, the French regularly expect
that the kings and emperors of Europe will be marching against
them with professional armies very soon,
and their fear is absolutely justified, and so is the
Athenian fear that the Spartans will be coming.
So it's in that hot environment, where fear is all
over the place, that this new democratic
constitution will be shaped. There's no question that,
I think, the place where it's happening is in the assembly.
The assembly sits as you, I hope you know,
on a hillside in the middle of Athens,
on a hill called the pynx and there in the
open air all adult male citizens are eligible to participate in
what takes place. One little point,
I'd also suggest to you, is what about the people who
have been thrown off the citizen lists?
Are they there? This is just my reasoning;
we don't have any hard evidence. My answer is absolutely they
are. Who is going to tell them not
to? You show up on the hill,
who's going to kick you off? Does Cleisthenes want you
kicked out? Hell no, because as we will
see, one of his main planks is enrolling those people as
citizens. So, in fact,
I will bet a lot of money that in all the electioneering that
went on about all these different things,
they were a group he must have targeted and said you've been
unfairly treated by these aristocrats.
If I get in power, I will see to it that you are
enrolled again as citizens. So, all of that is happening,
and people are very excited about what is going on.
That's the background for these rather dry and puzzling details
I'm about to lay on you to try to describe what these new laws
were that amounted to some kind of a democracy.
The center of them, apparently, was reforms of the
tribes, and they are in some ways very radical indeed.
As you know, these tribes go back before the
birth of history. Think of any primitive society
you want to; it's likely to be divided up
into tribes. The tribes typically are
alleged to come from some very ancient times when gods or
heroes founded them. That's certainly true of the
Greek tribes, where each tribe is named after
some heroic figure, some semi-divine figure in the
past. So, there are four,
the four traditional Ionian tribes, and that's why this is
even more radical than anything else.
Cleisthenes' law changes the tribal system in Athens from
four tribes to ten tribes, absolutely brand new things
that have no tradition behind them, nothing,
no history or anything. Then he has to give names to
these tribes, and according to the Greek
practice, these tribes have to have some founding hero to be
named after. So, he picks out,
I think I'm right in thinking, hundred names of heroes and he
assigns them to the ten tribes by lot,
and now you suddenly have ten new tribes.
Now, I mean, if you can try to think
yourself back to a tribal society and think about what a
disruptive thing this is. All my life I've been a member
of the tribe named after, Ion, and so have my ancestors,
and so my other ancestors. No more.
He's not around anymore; there's a new tribe that was
invented that I'm a member of. So, that's a very surprising
thing. But that's not the end of the
story; each tribe now is divided up
into three parts. The word for a third is
trittys and the plural is trittyes,
and here's the point. Each of the tribes has one of
its trittys in and around the city of Athens.
It has another one in the middle of Athens and it--I'm
sorry, in the middle of Attica and the third will be in the
region called the coast, the Peralia.
So every tribe is geographically distributed
across all of Attica, in this way that is something
quite new. In the old days we have to
believe that the tribes were geographically separated for
regions for tribes. The city region,
the coast region, and the midland region,
each one of these regions has ten trittyes,
one for each of the ten tribes. Now, let's take it a step
further, the trittyes themselves are formed of units
that are called demes. The Greek word for it,
and it's very confusing, is demos.
Now, the demos is this deme, this political
unit. It also means a village,
it also means the whole Athenian people,
and it also means only the poor Athenian people.
So, there you are. But in the context that we're
dealing with it here, we mean these units that are
geographical and have a constitutional function.
There is, however, even here a certain
amount of confusion, because some of the
demes are actually made up of an original village.
They don't mess with that. A deme is the equivalent
of a--in other words, a deme is a deme.
The two different meanings of the word deme;
other demes for the constitutional purpose are made
up of a number of villages. So, there would be a lot of
these old demes placed into the new constitutional
deme. The idea, however,
is that every trittys must be of the same size in
terms of population, because the whole idea is to
get each tribe to be numerically equal and one reason for that
is, because the tribes will be the
regiments of the Athenian army. You line up and fight in
your--when you're called to fight in the army in accordance
with your deme, which is located in the certain
trittys, which becomes a regiment.
Your tribe is a regiment of the army.
Now, get this straight, now the demes are
unequal in population but the trittyes have to be
equal, so that tells you you have to
have multiple demes in some and just one or two or a
few in another. It is also true that the
trittyes are assigned to the tribes by lot,
and the thing I want you to remember,
and I want to avoid as much complication as I can,
is that it doesn't really matter to the people who
invented the constitution, how the demes are assigned to
the trittyes, except one scholar has
suggested one motive that strikes most of us as very
plausible. He made a careful study of how
the demes had been distributed to the
trittyes and compared them with where we know there
were important religious sites. Greek religion has many
gods and deities and they have local characteristics,
because there are legends about their having lived on this
earth, at a certain place, or done a deed at another place.
So, you have a cave of Pan in eastern Attica,
and you have a place where Athena did this,
that, and the other thing, and the point I'm getting at is
these became shrines, places where the religion was
exercised in ancient Attica, aristocratic Attica.
The aristocrats owned a piece of land on which the shrine was,
which meant you had to have their permission to come onto it
to worship, which meant that they would
have predominance, power, and influence in these
areas. Well, what this scholar,
David Lewis was his name, concluded was that there are
quite a few times when the thing is laid out in such a way as to
divide the religious site on the aristocrats land from his main
dwelling on that land, so the aristocrat is separated
from the place where he has religious clout as a way of
dividing up his political influence and power.
He reads this as one of the ways in which Cleisthenes
attempted to diminish the power of the aristocracy through its
local influence. Now, this new deme
is very, very important. It is the basic unit in the
whole system. It was meant,
I should say, to take the place of the
phratry; you remember the brotherhood
that was kernel of the old tribal system.
It was meant that the deme should be the basic
thing. For instance,
one of the most important things was that your
citizenship, according to the laws of Cleisthenes,
was no longer to be ascertained by going to your phratry,
but each deme would keep an official roll of the citizens
in that deme. So, when an Athenian boy is
born, when he reaches a certain age, you have to take him to the
deme and register him, and now he can be an Athenian
citizen. Well, this was one of several
things that we see in Cleisthenes' constitution in
which the intention could not be carried out.
That is, the phratry, and the notion of the
phratry as the core of such things, was never
abolished; it would have been out of the
question to abolish it. It had too many religious
associations, and it never really lost its
place in the Athenian mind. Yes, your official enrollment
as a citizen was in the deme, but there was still
a tremendous allegiance to the phratry,
and the phratry was still run by aristocrats.
So, it didn't have its full effect.
The deme elected an official called a
demarche. We might call them mayor or
whatever the local official is called, select men we say
sometimes still in Connecticut, holding to our colonial
traditions. The deme is also given
religious functions and religious rights,
because everybody knows that religion still is potent,
even if you're engaged in a revolution in Athens at the
beginning of the fifth century. Here's another thing that they
tried to do. Cleisthenes tried with the law,
to change the way in which an Athenian was officially
designated. It used to be,
before Cleisthenes came along, you ask a man who are you.
He would say I am Cleisthenes, the son of Megacles.
Just the patronymic, just like you bear the name of
your father, unless you chose to bear the name of your mother,
which is evidence of how un-Athenian you really are. So, that's the way it was,
but under the laws of Cleisthenes, henceforth,
citizens were to be designated not as Cleisthenes,
son of Megacles, but as Cleisthenes from
Alopeke, which is to say his deme.
He was to be the citizen's name and his deme name. People have argued about what
the point of all this was, but I think one limited point,
before we get to the full story, is simply another way of
cutting down the influence of birth in the society.
It's a way of damaging the aristocratic principle and
asserting in its place--look what's really happening here,
that there is something which is the polis that has
nothing to do with birth that is the part of the legal structure
which is a polis. It's a whole new concept that's
really creeping in here, replacing the old traditional
way of organizing society with one that is the work of citizens
coming together and determining how they themselves will be
governed. Let that be the story of the
tribes for a moment. Now, here we go with
another council, you've heard about the council
of four hundred, you've heard about the council
of three hundred. We can do better than that;
we're going to have the council of five hundred.
It will be the council that is the democratic council for the
remainder of the history of the Athenian democracy,
with the exception of short periods of oligarchic rebellion
that remove it, but it comes back when the
democracy does. That council--let me simply
describe it very briefly. It is open to all Athenian
adult male citizens. Membership on the council comes
through some combination of allotment and election--the
point of it is that an assembly of thousands is not well
equipped to conduct all kinds of business that has to be
conducted for the state, and even its own business.
You need a smaller group to prepare the agenda for a full
assembly meeting, and so that was the function of
the five hundred. It is, and this is very
important, one of those very democratic elements,
the assembly of course was totally democratic,
because adult male citizens participate if they wish.
But you can easily get around that in some degree if you have
a council or little group that actually determines what's going
to happen. From the first it wasn't so.
The members of the council had to be--I'm sorry,
the council itself was as democratic as the assembly.
So, we'll come back to that council later on,
but there it is in place. Another thing that happened,
not in 508-7, but a few years down the road,
but still in the same period, was that by now the army of
Athens, which originally had been led simply by the
polemarch, the archon who was
chosen for the military leadership had given way to
generals who commanded the different tribes.
It used to be that each tribe elected its own general,
but in the new system now, the entire people elected the
generals for each of the tribes. In other words,
the ten tribes still had a general a piece,
but the entire population elected him.
Usually, he came from the tribe that he
was asked to command, but not always.
Again, you can see what the point of this is;
it has the same characteristic as so much of what we are
describing. It is going to reduce
particularism, localism, and make the whole
people, the whole demos and their represented
institutions be the decisive element in the state.
And that is one of the things we'll be getting to right next
to ask ourselves what's going on here and why is it happening.
Here, l will tell you what our sources say and at the end of
the day we have to make some judgments.
Of course, generally and I think properly,
the source who gets the most credence from scholars today is
Herodotus, who is closer to it in time
than, although he's--I should point out Herodotus is writing
his history sometime, and at least he's writing it as
late as the 420s, but he himself,
goes back to an earlier part of the fifth century.
Therefore, he is in a position to hear stories from people who
go back even into the sixth century,
which makes him theoretically a more credible source than people
like Aristotle, who I'll be quoting at you,
who lives in the fourth century and he's a good whole century
later than Herodotus. But Herodotus is not,
of course, himself a witness to any of the facts that he
adduces.Anyway, he asks why did Cleisthenes of
Athens do what he did. And his answer is a pretty
stale one. He was trying to copy his
ancestor Cleisthenes of Sicyon, who also changed the tribes,
you may remember in Sicyon, from the old Dorian tribes to
new tribes that designated the wrong people like--I mean to say
the Dorians as swine men and ass men,
and so on. That's why Cleisthenes did it,
and he thought it would be a nice thing to do because his
ancestor, his namesake, did the same thing.
Well, I don't think we can buy that.
We move into a more persuasive territory I think when we get to
Aristotle, who writes in his Politics as follows:
"perhaps a question rather arises,"
he's dealing with the whole question of citizenship,
"about those who had been admitted to citizenship after a
revolution had taken place. For instance such a creation of
citizens as that carried out at Athens by Cleisthenes,
after the expulsion of the tyrants, when he enrolled in his
tribes many resident aliens, metics,
who had been foreigners and slaves."
So, here's a new story that we have to add to the picture,
I mentioned it in passing, but it's very important.
One of the things Cleisthenes does,
and he has to do it through measures passed through the
assembly, is to enfranchise the people
who had been thrown off the citizen lists. One thing that you want to do,
and you couldn't have done that, given the nature of the
old constitution. If you hadn't broken up the old
system of tribes, phratres,
and so on, and come up with a new one
which would not have the old prejudices against it.
So, that's part of the story. Again, Aristotle or one of his
pupils--there's some dispute about the document that is
called the Constitution of Athens,
as to whether Aristotle was the composer of that piece or one of
his students. Anyway, here's what it says,
"with the aim of mixing up the population, so that a great
number would share ii the citizenship,
they came up with this phrase, me phylokrinein, do not
judge according to tribe." But it goes beyond tribe,
it really means, do not judge on the basis of
birth. Aristotle says it was
directed against those who wanted to check on family
background. He goes on to say this new
nomenclature, that's what I just mentioned to
you before about your name, that is, you are not the son of
so and so, but rather you are of the deme so and so.
He says, "so that they would not by addressing one another by
their father's names and expose the newly enrolled citizens,
but would call them by the families of the demes."
This passage caused a great deal of puzzle and confusion
among scholars who couldn't understand what this was all
about, and that's I think,
because the topic was mostly treated by the British.
But Americans can see this right away.
The best way to put it is this way--of course you wouldn't know
about this. You live in a country that is
absolutely pure and without prejudice, according to race or
color, or ethnic origins or religion;
so you won't know what I'm talking about.
But let me pass on from an earlier generation,
a darker time in which I grew.Suppose you're a man
who came from the Abruzzi in Italy,
and your name was Giovanni DeStefano.
That was fine in the Abruzzi, but in America there were
people that didn't have a high opinion of people with such a
name and were likely not to be opening their doors or homes to
people like that. So, your son instead of calling
himself Giovanni DeStefano changed his name to John
Stevens, and thereupon, everything was okay.
That' the way things were meant to be in Athens.
That is to say, the idea was if you had a
foreign sounding name, and your father would have a
foreign sounding name, if he came from a foreign place
when he settled in Attica. You would be branded in that
way and people who wanted, and here it was more specific,
to throw you off the citizen lists would know who you were,
but if you took a good solid Anglo Athenian name,
why, you'd be all right. So, I think that is the
explanation and it's all part of the same picture.
Taking away the traditional influences that would be
anti-democratic and replacing them with things that shattered
that, and taking away the local
powers, anything that smacked of the past, you try to erase as
best you can. The procedure,
we all agree, is by the device that the
Greeks called psephisma. It was a motion passed by the
assembly, and it comes to be the standard form of legislation in
the Athenian democracy, the plural of psephisma
is psephismata. Now, the scholar who I was
eluding to a few moments ago Lewis, he's got the general
picture right. He says we have to understand
all of this was passed on the assembly in a mood of great
excitement and fear, and anger, a revolutionary
situation in which he imagined alluding to the revolution in
St. Petersburg in 1917,
that they are getting up and shouting, "all power to the ten
tribes." To those of you who are not in
St. Petersburg, they were shouting,
"all power to the Soviets," but I think he's wrong.
It wasn't about the ten tribes. The ten tribes weren't the
issue. I think if they were shouting
and I guess they were, they were shouting all power to
the ecclesia, to the assembly.
That's where decisions were going to be made in the future.
But I do want you to take seriously the notion that the
making of such a claim and doing so in heated circumstances was
revolutionary, because without that,
it's inconceivable that what happened would have happened.
Now, let me go back to the boule;
it was elected by a lot from proportional representation in
the demes, all Athenians.
The Greek word for preparing legislation for an assembly is
probouleusis and such a group is probouleutic,
that is, it prepares legislation.
The chances are that this council was more powerful and
had more independence when it was invented,
than it would later on. That's just a guess,
but you know you're at the beginning of something.
You're still living in a society in which class
distinctions are very clear and very sharp,
in which the idea of the ordinary citizen taking things
into his own hands is new and scary.
I think there would have been a lot of deference paid to the
individuals who came from the higher classes,
and I would guess that they would have been on the
preliminary list that was elected before allotment
selected among them, and that when they proposed
something to the assembly, it would be given greater
influence on what happened subsequently than would be true.
When we get down to the full scale of Athenian democracy
in the time of Pericles forget about it.
The boule is the servant of the assembly,
without question. If the council sends in a
proposed law in certain language, the assembly can vote
it down or they can send it back to the boule and say,
no we don't like those words; change the words into this
direction, and then send it back to us.
That's the way it was in the full democracy.
My guess is it wasn't that way in the year 505.
I think it probably was meant by Cleisthenes to be a bit more
conservative without being, of course in any way,
reactionary. Now, what is this all about
in the larger sense? Lewis suggests that there's
something here that is personal and political and I think he's
right. One of the elements that he
suggests is these demes were not assigned to
trittyes accidentally, as I've suggested already,
but were carefully laid out not only to deprive noblemen of
their undue influence but he thinks probably to help
Cleisthenes and his Alcmaeonidae to have a powerful voice in as
much of Attica as he possibly could.
Why in the world would anybody doubt that?
That strikes me as being--that's what people do
when they have the power to help themselves politically they do.
I would guess, in other words,
Cleisthenes was thinking of his own political position in part.
Again, we don't have hard evidence for this,
but just a reasonable suggestion.
Now, the other thing is, we have to, I think,
believe, that this whole program of reform was supported
by what we have been referring to all along,
the hoplite class, these independent farmers.
They are the ones who are most numerous.
They are among those who will be politically active.
Also, they are of course the defense of Athens now,
they have to be taken very seriously and they are not about
to allow themselves to be cut out or to have their own
influence diminished by things that are hanging over from the
days of aristocracy. So, I think we should think of
this and I think just about everybody does.
They like to designate this Cleisthenic democracy,
this first democracy, as a hoplite democracy,
and saying that the hoplites were in means that to some
considerable degree, the poor are out.
The chances are very great; I would say pretty certain,
that the majority of citizens, the majority of Athenian
citizens, were not hoplites. They were thetes.
There probably never was a time when the hoplites were a
majority even in Athens. So, excluding them certainly is
a limit on what you want to call democracy, and here's where we
get into sort of the debates these days.
Many, many a scholar--now that the academy is essentially a
branch of the Politburo will want to denigrate ancient
Athenian democracy and to suggest it really wasn't
democratic. Well, there are twenty million
ways you can do that. You can talk about the fact
that it excluded women, you can talk about the fact
that it--who else does it exclude?
That it had slaves, excluded slaves,
it excluded resident aliens, and all those things and then
you can finally point to the fact that probably the majority
of the adult male citizens were excluded from some important
elements in the democracy, although as time passes that
last disappears, and you have pretty much
complete participation by the poor,
but in Cleisthenes case that's not so.
But I think that's to be deliberately blind to what's
really happening. What you have is a miracle.
Nothing in the world that we know of anywhere,
ever like this has ever been seen before.
The reaction of the other Greeks as best we can figure out
was horror. This is wild and crazy,
the stuff that the Athenians are doing, it is radical,
it is dangerous. We must contain ourselves and
avoid being in touch with them, or we should try to finish
those guys off. Certainly that was the attitude
the Spartans typically had towards it, and undoubtedly the
normal Greek government, which was an oligarchy,
certainly took the same point of view.
So, I think you can look at it from either direction,
probably should look at it from both,
but don't miss the point that what's happening here is of this
very special character. What did they call this
constitution? Well, we don't know.
But the chances are great that they did not call it democracy.
The word democracy, our word democracy comes from
the Greek demokratia, which I guess you would want to
translate as something like power for the masses,
for the people at large, or the people as a whole.
But it was a name that was given to the Athenian
constitution by a people who didn't like it.
What did they think of themselves?
Well, Herodotus refers to this regime as one of
eisonomia, equality of law,
and I think the thing that's most important about it is,
equality before the law. That is, something that wipes
out distinctions among classes of people on the basis when it
comes to the law. Every man who comes before the
law is equal to every other man. Well, that's a very big change
that no place else in the world had, and I think that's not a
bad way to think of it. Now, of the principles that
belonged from the first to this democracy, and was maybe as
crucial as anything in characterizing it was what they
called isegoria, equality of speech really.
It meant equality of the opportunity to address the
political body, meaning the assembly.
Every Athenian male from the first adult regardless of what
his money rating was, of his class,
whether he was a thete or higher, everyone had the
right to speak in the assembly. Now, this had been a right that
was limited of course to aristocrats in many cities,
or to the wealthy in other cities.
But we know from some of the poems in the sixth century,
it was prized as the evidence that an individual was a free
man as opposed to a slave. He could get up in the center,
that was the term they used, of the town,
meaning wherever the meeting place was,
and then speak his mind and also try to persuade his fellow
citizens to do as he thought best.
We should not take this lightly.
In our world, where we never imagine
ourselves in such a situation, it's hard to grasp but actually
to think. If I want to I can get out
there during the debate that's going to decide what happens.
I can say what I have to say. So, freedom of speech is very,
very central to the Athenian idea of self government. The role of the boule in
place of aristocratic councils enhances the democracy.
On the other hand, things did not happen that you
might think would happen. Nothing was done in the sphere
of the economy. There was no change in Solonian
classes or privileges. You still had to have a certain
amount of money to be elected to the top things in the state.
The Areopagus was left untouched, remaining a
collection of former magistrates, all of whom had
been aristocrats. The phratres,
the homes of aristocracy were left intact.
You had this hoplite democracy, which was indeed democracy,
but we must imagine, I think all the evidence would
support this imagination, that it was a deferential
democracy in which the lower classes still looked up to the
upper classes for leadership and guidance,
and they themselves did not hold leading positions in the
state. I think that's the picture we
have. Well, let me turn at last
to one of the most interesting features of the constitution
introduced by Cleisthenes; gives us a picture of how
things worked that we wouldn't get any other way.
I'm talking abut the law that was passed on ostracism.
Our word ostracism derives from it, but it's something quite
different. If somebody says we're going to
ostracize this guy today, it means we're not going to
invite him for a drink; we're not going to go to his
parties, things like that. No this was something far
different and was a central part of the political system.
Let me begin by simply describing how it worked.
Every year, let us say in the month of January,
that's the way the Athenian calendar would have made it come
out more or less typically, a question came up in the
assembly automatically. Nobody had to move it;
it was an automatic thing. The question was,
"Shall we have an ostracism this year?"
Now, they could debate that question, but what they were not
debating was who should we ostracize.
That was not at issue. The only question was,
should we have one this year? If a majority said yes,
then they would go on. If they majority said no,
that was it, no ostracism that year.
But supposing a majority had voted for an ostracism,
now we go to roughly the month of March and let's go down to
the center of town, the agora,
which is the marketplace, which is the political center
which is where people go to talk and all those things.
That's where the action is, and for that day and that day
alone, the agora is fenced off,
and there are ten gates in the fences, one for each tribe,
and every citizen who wishes, goes with a piece of broken
pottery. Someone has described it as the
scrap paper of antiquity, and with whatever you could
get, piece of glass,
crayon, or whatever, you would simply write the name
of a man that you would like to see ostracized that year.
You would go to the gate. There would be some people at
the gate, who would identify are you really a citizen,
where are you coming from and all that.
You, then, handed in your ostraka and you went
inside the agora, where you stayed until the
voting was over so that you couldn't come back and vote
again. Now, they were cleverer than
the people of Florida are today. So, now it's over,
the time has come, and what they do is they divide
up all the ostraka that have been cast.
They don't divide them up I'm sorry.
They put them in a big pile and count them.
If there are fewer than 6,000 ballots, nobody gets ostracized.
If there are 6,000 or more, now they divide them up into
piles, and the one who gets the most votes,
not majority, just the highest number of
votes plurality, he wins.
He gets ostracized.What does that mean?
It means that he must leave Attica, at a certain distance
from Attica, for ten years. That's all.
He has been accused of no crime; therefore, he has been
convicted of no crime. Nothing is done to his property;
nothing is done to his family. At the end of ten years,
he may come back and it's as though he never left.
The next day, if he wants to,
he can run for public office. That's all;
that is ostracism. What's this all about?
What are the purposes of this thing?
Well, I think the best way to come at this is to tell you a
couple of stories and some facts.
The story I guess comes from Plutarch's Life of
Aristides, who is one of the leading
Athenian figures at the early part of the fifth century,
and who in fact was a man who was ultimately ostracized.
The story goes like this. It's ostracism day in Athens,
and some country bumpkin, some rube comes walking up,
and he spots Aristides chatting with some folks and he goes up
to Aristides and he says, "excuse me sir I don't know how
to write, would you please write a name on this potsherd for me?"
Aristides, of course, a gentleman he says,
"certainly sir, what name would you like?"
He said, "Aristides please." "Oh," he says,
and he writes down Aristides, and by the way he said,
"what is it that you have against Aristides?"
I should have told you that Aristides had earned this
sobriquet, the just Aristides,
Aristides the just. So, the guy says,
"what have you got against Aristides?
I have nothing against Aristides, I've never seen the
man, don't know him. I'm just so damn tired of
hearing him called the just." The point of that story is to
illustrate Plutarch's point is that the system of ostracism was
just a piece of silly foolishness that you would
associate with democracy, which just allowed the jealousy
of the ordinary man for superior people to determine what's going
on. That's the message that
Plutarch gets from that tale. Here's another piece of
information; that's not a tale.
I think it was about 1937,1938 an American archaeologist was
working up on the north slope of the Acropolis and he came upon a
well, he dug into the well,
and out came 191 inscribed potsherds, ostraka with
but one name written on all of them,
and that name was Themistocles, who we know was a participant
in a batch of ostraka in the 480s,
and careful analysis of the handwriting indicated that these
191 ostraka were inscribed by 14 hands writing
them. Is it beginning to sound
familiar to you guys, I suppose.
The best guess of everybody who studies these things is that we
do not have here the remains of a collection of voters,
who voted and had their votes counted and then these came,
but rather that these were votes that never were cast
actually. So what's going on here?
Now, I turn from my attempt at a factual account of what
happened in the past to fiction. The rest of this is my
imagination. We find ourselves down the
middle of Athens, the day before the ostracism.
We are in the home of John the potter who is a charter member
of the Aristides political club, and what they are doing is
sitting about chatting as they incise or paint the name onto a
ostrakon, the name is Themistocles.
Next day, down there outside the Agora, various country
bumpkins and others are wandering into town.
You step up to one of them and say;
perhaps you would like to vote in the ostracism today sir?
I can save you the trouble of inscribing your ballot,
here's one right now. I think this is pretty good
evidence that they're talking about organized political
activities, which in fact I think totally
squares with what we know about the purpose of ostracism.
I should tell you one other thing, that Thucydides himself
says something very important about this.
He says, ostracism was brought about, because of the fear and
the insecurity that the Athenians felt about their
democracy, that it was in constant danger,
and that they needed something to help them.
That's the context in which he used it.
Plutarch, as I say, has a more general story,
the envy and jealousy natural to democracy.
You must realize that hardly anybody who ever wrote anything
in antiquity had a kind word to say for democracy;
it's a bad thing from the standpoint of most of the
authors of antiquity. But Thucydides was there,
while ostracism was a reality, as opposed to Plutarch,
and I'm sure he is right. Let's look,
first of all, at the moment when ostracism
was invented in the time of Cleisthenes, before we move
beyond that. What's the situation?
Cleisthenes and company have just brought about this unique,
amazing, and to the rest of the world dangerous coup
d'état, and invented this new wild
crazy kind of government. They know that the Spartans are
furious and they expect they're going to come down anytime.
They also know that in Athens, there are people who don't like
this new government. Some of them are the heirs to
the old aristocracy. Some of them are aristocrats
themselves. Others were very happy in the
days of the tyranny. In fact, there are still
relatives of the tyrants, eminent ones,
who are still in Athens. In other words,
they have to fear betrayal, they have to fear internal
hostility, and they have to fear people who might start a civil
war. At the same time as they have
to be afraid of the Spartans coming up the road,
and we know, because in a few years this is
going to happen, they have enemies of other
neighboring states. Corinthians,
the Eretrians, Boeotians, Thebes,
and others within the next five years--they will have invasions
by those people as well. That's their situation,
what are they afraid of? They are afraid that there will
be treason inside the city, which will help invaders or
simply turn the city over to them.
Well then, why don't they just lock these guys up?
Well, in the first place, they probably haven't done
anything yet, and you couldn't make a case
against them. On top of which,
you really don't, if you're Cleisthenes,
you don't want to treat all of these people as though they are
the enemies of the new regime. They are, in fact,
natural opponents, the friends of the tyrants and
the old aristocrats; they're on opposite sides of
the argument. Why would you want to put them
together by assaulting their leaders?
A smarter thing would be to try to win over one faction to
support your side at the expense of the other.
That is my guess as to what is another explanation of what's
happening here. So, here's another piece of
fiction I want to throw at you. I imagine that Cleisthenes
stops by at the house of Hipparchus, the son of Karmas,
who is a relative of the Peisistratids and who would be
looked to as the leading figure in that faction,
and he stops by to see Hipparchus, and Hipparchus says,
"hello Cleisthenes, say what is this routine,
what is this crazy new law that you and your boys just put
through, this ostracism law?
I hear in the streets that it's aimed at me, as the leader of
the old tyranny faction, what is that?"
Cleisthenes I imagine would say, "Now, where did you get a
crazy idea like that? I mean, you're a swell fellow,
I'm only against these terrible aristos out there,
and their Spartan lackeys, who are going to take away all
the people's rights and I know you wouldn't want that to
happen, that's not like you.
So, of course I can see your point, I can see you are
alarmed, I can see that people might say,
gee those old Peisistratids might be trying to overthrow
this new democracy, and bring themselves back in.
I know Hippeis is over there in Persia, supported by the king
and maybe people would think you're for bringing him back as
a tyrant. I knew that would never be in
your mind, but I tell you what you ought to do,
why don't you come over to my side and I'll see to it--you
know I have friends, I got a lot of friends.
I could do you a favor. You do me a favor;
I can do you a favor. I can see to it that I would
just kill that rumor, and everything would be very
happy." The next day all is well.
I think there's considerable evidence.
I don't have time for it now--not certain,
but evidence suggesting that Hipparchus came on board and
became part of a coalition that ruled Athens for decades after
that time. And so, that year there was no
ostracism, because there didn't have to be an ostracism.
I think that is very important. Most years there was no
ostracism, only once in a while, and every single person that we
hear ostracized was a leading political figure.
Ostracism, in short, was meant to be a
constitutional device to work in the political realm as a way of
deterring a coup d'état,
treason or other forms of unrest.
You could only use it as a politician if you were the
popular favorite. If you were confident that the
ostracism would go your way, if you held an ostracism and
that wasn't true, you might find yourself
traveling a long way from home pretty soon, and so that's the
essence of ostracism and we'll have a look at it again because
it crops up and is used but not for twenty years after it's
invented. Okay.