Professor Steven Smith:
Because it's a makeup class, we'll do something a little
special. We're going to show a clip from
a movie that I think is particularly appropriate.
As we get into it, I'll tell you why.
It's about a five-minute segment from the film called
The Third Man. Has anyone ever seen it?
Okay, maybe more than I thought. Just to set up the scene,
for those of you have seen it and more for those of you who
haven't, this is a film that was made in
1948 called The Third Man from a Graham Greene short
story. It takes place in post World
War II Vienna. And the clip we're going to see
is the most famous part of the movie.
It takes place of a conversation between two old
friends. One of them,
played by Orson Welles, is in a black market racket in
Vienna and is making a living doing something very bad in the
black market. In this scene,
he's trying to convince an old school friend of his,
played by Joseph Cotten, to join this thing.
I should say the Orson Welles character has also faked his
death, so no one except his immediate conspirators knows
he's still alive. I should have said that.
He's faked his death and here he has a scene with his old
school friend, played by Joseph Cotten,
and he's trying to convince him to come into his black market
racket. So here comes The Third
Man. Good scene.
It's good because I think it conveys something of the flavor
of Machiavelli's thought in Italy for 30 years under the
Borgias. This is Machiavelli's time.
Blood shed and murder and Leonardo da Vinci and the Renais
sance. Under Switzerland for 500
years, peace and democracy. What did it produce?
The cuckoo clock. I'm going to talk about that in
a moment. I want to begin by talking
about who was Machiavelli. How do we read The
Prince? Machiavelli was a Florentine.
To know that is to know virtually everything you need to
know about him. I'm exaggerating but I do so to
make a point. Florence was a republic.
It was a city-state. And Machiavelli spent a good
deal of his adult life in the service of the republic.
Living in Florence, the center of the Renaissance
at the height of the Renais sance,
Machiavelli wished to do for politics what his
contemporaries, like Leonardo da Vinci and
Michelangelo, had done for art and sculpture.
In other words, he hoped to revive in some way
the spirit of the ancients of antiquity, but to modify it in
the lights of his own experience.
As he puts it in the dedication of his most famous book,
he writes that this book The Prince "is a product of long
experience with modern things and a continuous reading of the
ancient ones." In Machiavelli,
we have what we have come to call "modernity," given its
first and most powerful expres sion.
But Machiavelli was not an ordinary Florentine.
He grew up under the rule of the Medici.
That is to say, the first family of Florence,
and lived to see them deposed by a Dominican friar by the name
of Savonarola. Savonarola attempted to impose
a kind of theocracy in Florence, a sort of Christian republic of
virtue. But the Florentines,
being what they were, rejected this idea and the rule
of Savonarola was short-lived. In its place,
a republic was re-established where Machiavelli occupied the
office of secretary to the second chancery,
a kind of diplomatic post which he held for 14 years from 1498
to 1512. After the fall of the republic
and the return of the Medici to princely rule there,
Machiavelli was exiled from the city, from politics to a small
estate that he owned on the out skirts of the city.
You can visit it today. It was here,
from a place of political exile, that he wrote his major
works--The Prince, the Discourses on
Livy, and The Art of War. It was from here,
also, that he wrote voluminous letters to friends seeking
knowledge about politics. Machiavelli was a kind of
political junkie, you could say,
in things happening in Italy and else where.
In one of these letters, a famous letter to his friend,
a man named Francesco Vettori, he describes how he came to
write his most famous book. I want to read a passage from
that letter. It is also, I should say,
on the basis of this letter, which is why I ask people from
time to time to remove their caps in the class room,
from the House of Study. This is the way Machiavelli
approached study. "When evening comes,"--he
writes, "When evening comes, I return to my house and go to
my study. At the door,
I take off my clothes of the day covered with muck and dirt
and I put on my regal and courtly garments.
And decently reclothed, I enter the ancient courts of
ancient men, where received by them lovingly,
I feed on the food that alone is mine and that I was born for.
There I am not ashamed to speak with them and to ask them the
reasons for their actions and they, in their humanity,
reply to me. And for the space of four hours
every night, I feel no boredom. I forget every pain.
I do not fear poverty and death does not frighten me.
I deliver myself entirely unto them.
And because Dante says that to have understood without
retention does not make knowledge,
I have noted what capital I have made from their
conversations and have composed a little work on principalities,
where I delve as deeply as I can into reflections on this
subject, debating what a principality is,
of what kinds they are, how they are acquired,
how they are maintained, and why they are lost.
So there, Machiavelli gives us a sense of the seriousness with
which he approached his subject, how he studied,
and what it was he came to write.
Let me just say from the beginning, The Prince is
a deceptive book. What else would we expect from
the name of a man that has become synonymous with
deception? It is a work,
The Prince, that everybody has heard of,
perhaps has some preconception about.
I was checking the web yesterday and I found a new book
about Machiavelli, which none of these every fail
to surprise me. This one is called The Suit:
a Machiavellian Guide to Men's Fashion. Check it out.
Who knows? Machiavelli's name is
everywhere. It is applied to everything,
from corporate executives now to men's fashion.
Everybody knows or thinks they know what his work is about.
His name, again, is synonymous with deception,
treachery, cunning, deceit.
Just look at the cover of your book.
Look at his face. Look at his smile,
really more of a smirk. He seems to be saying,
"I know something you don't know."
The difficulty with reading Machiavelli today is that we all
think we already know what he knows and that is false.
Machiavelli was a revolutionary. In the preface to his largest
book, the Discourses on Livy, he compares himself to
Christopher Columbus for his discovery of what he calls "new
modes and orders." What Columbus had done for
geography, Machiavelli claims he will do for politics.
That is to say, discover an entirely new
continent, a new world, so to speak,
the new world of Machiavelli. Machiavelli's new world,
his new modes and orders, will require,
clearly, a displacement of the earlier one, of the previous
one. And Machiavelli wrote,
of course, the dominant form of political organization was the
empire or, to speak more precisely, the Christian empire.
The Holy Roman Empire, as it was known in the time of
Machiavelli, was the successor to the ancient Roman state,
the older Roman Empire. Both of these empires had
aspired to a kind of universality.
And this universality was given expression in Dante's famous
treatise, De Monarchia, of monarchy,
that set out a model for a universal Christian state,
based on the unity and oneness of the human race under a
Christian ruler. Machiavelli rejected this idea
of the empire and harked back, instead, to the model of
republican Rome. And there is much in his
writing that recalls the sort of extraordinary virtues and
capacities of the citizens of the ancient republican
city-state. But you might say just as
Machiavelli broke with the dominant model of Christian
universalism, so too did he reject the
ancient model of the small, autonomous republican state.
He makes this clear in a famous passage at the beginning of
chapter 15 of The Prince. And I just want to read that
passage, as well. Here, Machiavelli says,
"I depart from the orders of others.
I depart from their modes," he says.
"But since it is my intent to write something useful to
whoever understands it, it has appeared to me more
fitting to go directly to the effectual truth of things than
to the imagination of it. And many have imagined," --one
thinks here of Plato, perhaps, but also to
Christianity--"Many have imagined republics and
principalities that have never been seen or known to exist in
truth. For it is far from how one
lives to how one should live. That he who lets go of what is
done for what should be done learns his ruin rather than his
preservation." In other words,
no Platonic cities in speech. No Augustinian cities of God.
We will only look, he says, to the effectual truth
of things. The effectual truth of the
matter, not the imagination of it or the utopia of it.
That passage is often taken to be, the beginning of chapter 15,
the essence of Machiavelli and realism, a kind of
Realpolitik, as it were.
His appeal from the "ought" to the "is," to take one's bearings
again, from the effectual truth of things.
This seems to be, in many ways,
the essence of his teaching. To be sure, Machiavelli focuses
on key aspects of political reality which are often ignored
by thinkers like Plato and Aristotle.
Murders, conspiracies, coup d'état,
these are the kinds of political phenomena he is
interested. He seems to be more interested
in the evils that human beings do than the goods to which they
aspire. You might even say that
Machiavelli takes delight in demonstrating,
much to our chagrin, the space between our lofty
intentions and the actual consequences of our deeds.
Yet, it would seem to me there is more to Machiavelli than the
term "realism" connotes, although that is certainly
important. In this passage,
Machiavelli announces his break, indeed his repudiation of
all those who have come before, all those who have come before.
He both replaces and yet reconfigures according to his
own lights, elements from both the Christian empire and the
Roman republic, to create a new form of
political organization distinctly his own.
What we might call today the modern state.
Machiavelli is the founder, the discoverer,
the inventor of the modern state. This modern,
secular, sovereign state was refined and developed in the
decades and centuries after Machiavelli in the writing of
Hobbes, of Locke, of Rousseau,
to say nothing of contemporary twentieth-century writers from
both the right and the left--Max Weber,
Karl Schmidt, to a man, an Italian
philosopher named Antonio Gramsci, who was the author of a
book interestingly called The Modern Prince,
based on Machiavelli himself. Machiavelli's state itself has
universalist ambitions, in many ways,
much like its Christian and Roman predecessors.
But this is a state, he believes,
that has now been liberated or emancipated from Christian and
classical conceptions of virtue. The management of affairs is
left to those people who he calls princes,
which in the Machiavellian usage designates a new kind of
political founder or leader endowed with a new species of
ambition, love of glory,
and elements of prophetic authority that we might call
charisma. But just what was the nature of
the revolution contemplated by our founder, Machiavelli,
the founder of modern political science?
Consider, just for a moment, the title and dedication of the
book. The Prince appears,
on its surface, to be a most conventional work.
It presents itself in the long tradition of what has come to be
called the mirror of princes. Books that give a kind of guide
to the dos and don'ts of princely behavior.
Fair enough. It seems to go back a long,
long time. And the appearance of
conventionality is supported by the opening words of the book in
his dedicatory letter. The first words or first line
out of his mouth or the first lines are "it is customary," he
says. It is a work intended to
ingratiate himself to Lorenzo de Medici, the man to whom the work
is dedicated, a customary prince,
a traditional prince who has just regained his power.
But look again. Consider the structure of the
first three chapters. "All states,
all dominions that have held and do hold empire over man are
either republics or principalities,"
he says in the opening sentence of chapter 1.
Having distinguished two, and only two,
kinds of regimes, republics and principalities,
as the only ones worth mentioning, he goes on to
distinguish two kinds of principalities.
There are hereditary principalities,
like those currently run by Lorenzo, which acquire their
authority through tradition and hereditary bloodlines.
Then he says there are new princes and new principalities.
Machiavelli then asserts that his book will deal only with
principalities, leaving,
he says, the discussion of republics for elsewhere,
what one assumes his Discourses of Livy,
which he was already writing by this time.
But then Machiavelli goes on to tell the reader that the
exclusive subject of this book will be the new prince.
In other words, not Lorenzo at all,
but precisely princes who have or will achieve their authority
through their own guile, their own force,
or their own virtù, to use the famous Machiavellian
term that I want to talk about later.
The true, in other words, recipient of this book must be
necessarily the potential prince.
That is to say, someone with sufficient
political audacity to create their own authority,
who has not simply received it from the past,
but to create their own authority.
Maybe one could even say Machiavelli's prince is,
in a way, the first truly self-made man. So what, then,
is the character of this new prince and how does he differ
from more conventional modes of political authority?
In one of the most famous chapters of the book,
chapter 6, entitled, "Of New Principalities that are
Acquired Through One's Own Arms and Virtue,"
there is that word again, virtù,
one's own arms and virtue, Machiavelli discusses the
character of the modern prince, the new prince.
"A prudent man," he writes, "should always enter upon the
paths beaten by great men and imitate those who have been most
excellent, so that if his own virtue does
not reach that far, it at least is in the odor of
it." We at least come within,
you might say, sniffing distance of their
greatness. "One should do," he says,
"what archers do when attempting to reach a distant
target, namely, aim your bow high,
knowing that the force of gravity will bring the arrow
down." In other words,
set your sights high, knowing you will probably fall
short. "So who are the greatest
examples," he says, "of princely rule that the
prudent man"--interesting choice of words,
"the prudent man"--"should imitate?"
And here, Machiavelli gives a list of those heroic founders of
peoples and states--Moses, Cyrus, Romulus,
Theseus, and so on. "As one examines their actions
and lives," he writes, "one does not see that they had
anything else from fortune than the opportunity which gave them
the matter enabling them to introduce any form they please.
Notice in that sentence, he uses those Aristotelian
terms, "form" and "matter" that we spoke about in relation to
the Aristotelian regime. "They had nothing else from
fortune," he says, again, "than the opportunity,"
the occasion, that "gave them the matter
enabling them to introduce any form they please."
In short, Machiavelli claims these were founders who created,
in a way, ex nihilo, out of nothing.
They only had the occasion in a kind of formless matter upon
which they could adopt and impose any form they took.
And they had, of course, the strength of
mind, as well as the audacity and cunning, to take advantage
of this situation. Such opportunities,
he writes, such occasions, made these men successful.
And their excellent virtue enabled the opportunity to be
recognized. Hence, their fatherlands were
ennobled by it and they became prosperous. They took advantage of their
opportunity, seized their opportunity and imposed their
own form upon it. And it is here that Machiavelli
introduces his famous distinction between armed and
unarmed prophets. "All the armed prophets," he
says, "conquered and the unarmed were ruined."
This seems to be and is, clearly, a kind of classic
statement of sheer Machiavellian power politics.
"All politics grows out of the barrel of a gun," as a famous
twentieth-century Machiavellian once put it.
The armed prophets conquer, the unarmed lose.
But there seems to be more to it than this.
Machiavelli compares the prince to a prophet.
Why does he use that language? What is a prophet?
The most obvious answer is a person to whom God speaks.
Machiavelli's armed prophets may not be religious figures and
they are not necessarily recipients of divine knowledge,
but they seem to be, at least on his account,
people of exceptional personal qualities that allow them to
bring laws, to be law bringers,
lawgivers, shapers of institutions and also reformers
of opinions that govern our lives.
Machiavelli's armed prophet is more than just a gangster,
like Orson Welles in that part. He is a teacher and a kind of
educator as well. You might even think in your
class, in your sections, how or in what ways does
Machiavelli's armed prophet differ in important ways both
from Plato's philosopher king, as well as Aristotle's notion
of the megalopsychos as the sort of magnanimous
statesman. Although this kind of talk
about "armed prophets always win" is characteristic of
Machiavelli, he likes this kind of tough talk.
He clearly recognizes that there are clear exceptions to
his rule about armed prophets. Who comes to mind most vividly?
Who, in other words, is not present in Machiavelli's
list of great prophets that one should imitate?
Student: Jesus. Professor Steven Smith:
Yes. Most obvious,
perhaps, certainly to his contemporaries,
Jesus, who triumphed through words and teaching alone.
He had no troops. He had no arms.
He established a religion, first a sect,
you might say, then a religion,
then eventually an empire, the Holy Roman Empire,
that was established in the name of that teaching.
Words may well be a powerful weapon, as powerful as a gun.
Then you might say, "What is Machiavelli himself?"
Who is Machiavelli but an archetypal, unarmed prophet?
He has no troops. He has no territory.
He controls no real estate. He's been banished,
yet he is clearly attempting to conquer, comparing himself to
Columbus, to conquer in large part
through the transformation of our understanding of good and
evil, of virtue and vice.
In other words, to make people obey you,
you must first make them believe you.
Machiavelli's prophetic prince, in other words,
must have some of the qualities of a philosopher,
as well as a religious reformer trying to reshape and remold
human opinion, especially opinion over,
as we said, good and evil, just and unjust.
What does this reformation, so to speak,
or transformation consist of? We might even call this
Machiavelli in the garden of good and evil,
midnight in the garden of good and evil for Machiavelli. One point often attributed
about Machiavelli is that he introduced a new kind of
immoralism into politics. In that famous chapter,
chapter 15, he says he sets out to teach the prince how not to
be good. A striking formulation.
He will teach the prince how not to be good.
And in perhaps the most important book on Machiavelli
ever written, the author of that book
declared Machiavelli to be a teacher of evil.
You might want to think about that.
A teacher of evil. Is that what Machiavelli was?
Questions of good and bad, virtue and vice,
appear on virtually every page of The Prince.
He is not simply a teacher of political pragmatism,
of how to adjust means to fit the ends.
He seems to be offering nothing short of a comprehensive
revolution, transformation. If you want to use the
Nietzschean language, "transvaluation" of our most
basic vocabulary about good and evil.
Machiavelli doesn't reject the idea of the good.
Rather, he redefines it. He is continually speaking,
and in fact I would suggest on virtually every page of the
book, he is continually speaking the language of virtue.
His word "virtù," which a word that retains the Latin word for
the word "man," vir, wir,
man, and virtù, a word that is perhaps best
translated or, by our word, "manliness."
What distinguishes Machiavelli's use of this
language of virtù, manliness,
is that he seeks to locate it in certain extreme situations,
such as political foundings, changes of regimes,
wars, both of domestic and foreign kinds.
What distinguishes Machiavelli from his predecessors,
in many ways, is his attempt to take the
extraordinary situation, the extreme situation,
again, the extremes of political founding,
conspiracies, wars, coups,
as the normal situation and then makes morality fit that
extreme. His examples are typically
drawn from situations of human beings or polities in extremes
where the very survival or independence of a society is at
stake. In those situations,
you might say, and only in those situations,
is it permissible to violate the precepts of ordinary
morality. In those situations one must
learn, as he says, how not to be good,
to have to violate the conventions and cannons of
ordinary morality. Machiavelli takes his bearings
from these extreme states of emergency and in his own way,
seeks to normalize them, to present them as the normal
condition of politics. Machiavelli's preference for
these extreme situations expresses his belief that only
in moments of great crisis, where the very existence of a
state is at risk, does human nature truly reveal
itself. We finally or fully understand
what people are only in the most extreme situations.
The paradox that, you might say,
runs throughout all of Machiavelli's morality is that
the very possibility of virtue grows out of and,
in fact, is even dependent upon the context of chaos,
violence, and disorder that always threatens the political
world. Think of it.
Think of many of our great political models or heroes.
What would the Duke of Marlborough have been without
Louis XIV? What would Washington have been
without George III? What would Lincoln have been
without the slave interest? What would Churchill have been
without Hitler? In other words,
his point is that good is only possible because of the prior
existence of bad. Good is founded upon evil.
And even the greatest goods, the founding and preservation
of cities, often require murder. What was Romulus' murder of
Remus or Cain's murder of Abel, but the kind of murder that
founded, at the basis of the founding of
cities and civilizations? One thinks, in a way,
of Welles' line in The Third Man when he looks down from
above and says, "If I gave you 20,000 pounds
for every dot that stopped moving, would you really tell me
to keep my money?" It requires,
for Machiavelli, the founding of regimes
requires that kind of cold and cruel calculation. Of course, it's being used in
the movie just to support a criminal enterprise,
not the founding of a city. We might investigate that as
well. But Machiavelli does not deny
that in ordinary terms, in what we might call times of
normal politics, the ordinary rules of justice
prevail. He also shows,
however, that normal politics is, itself, dependent upon
extraordinary politics, periods of crisis,
anarchy, instability, revolution, where the normal
rules of the game are suspended. It is in these times,
you might say, when individuals of
extraordinary virtue and capacity,
prophetic qualities, as he calls it in chapter 6,
are most likely to emerge. While the Aristotelian
statesmen, just to make a contrast for a moment,
is most likely to value stability and the means
necessary to achieving it, the Machiavellian prince seeks
war, because it is only, again, in the most extreme
situations that one can prosper and be prosperous.
Think about the lines again from the movie.
"For 30 years under the Borgias, violence,
murder, terror, bloodshed.
But what did it produce? Greatness of an unprecedented
type. Stability, democracy,
brotherly love, peace.
What does that produce? Mediocrity, the cuckoo clock."
There might be a little more of Nietzsche suggested in that,
than Machiavelli, but I think the Machiavellian
overtones are very evident. Consider just the following.
Every child, every one of you,
every one of us was brought up to know that one must never do
wrong, even if good consequences are seen to follow.
It is never right to give bad examples to others,
even if one expects good to come from it.
Yet, Machiavelli breaks these rules about not giving bad
examples. Virtue is not associated with
the classical conceptions of moderation, of justice,
of self-control over the Christian virtues of faith,
hope, and charity. Virtue means for him a kind of
manly self-assertion, audacity, ruthlessness,
a reliance on one's own arms and calculated use of cruelty to
achieve one's ends. The model of Machiavellian
virtù is the Renaissance statesman, in general,
Cesare Borgia. It's very interesting that
Orson Welles made a movie, not so often seen today,
about Cesare Borgia. I want to leave you with
reading one passage from The Prince, chapter 7,
in which Machiavelli illustrates the kind of
virtù Cesare represented and that he wants to recommend
for those who follow him. "Once the duke," that's Cesare
himself--"Once the duke had taken over the Romana,"
an area outside of Florence, "he found it had been commanded
by impotent lords who had been readier to despoil their
subjects than to correct them and had given their subjects
matter for disunion, not union.
So Cesare put there," he says "Messer Ramiro d'Orco,
a cruel and ready man to whom he gave the fullest power."
So Cesare set up as a lieutenant of his to impose
order on this area and to whom he delegated the fullest
responsibility. "In short time," he goes on,
"Ramiro reduced it to peace and unity with the very greatest
reputation for himself. Then the duke judged that such
excessive authority was not necessary, because he feared it
might become hateful and he set up a sort of a civil court in
the middle of the province with the most excellent president
where each city had its advocate.
And because he knew that the past rigors had generated some
hatred for Ramiro, to purge the spirits of that
people and to gain them entirely to himself, he wishes to show
that if any cruelty had been committed,
this had not come from him, from Cesare,
but from the harsh nature of his minister.
And having seized this opportunity," that language,
seized the occasion, seized this opportunity,
"he had emplaced one morning in the piazza in two pieces,
with a piece of wood and a bloody knife beside him.
He had him cut in two. The bloody knife and piece of
wood beside him. "The ferocity of this
spectacle," Machiavelli concludes, "left the people at
once satisfied and stupefied." That, of course,
is Machiavelli's virtù, princely virtue,
what you do to leave the people satisfied and stupefied.
What we might call today shock and awe.
Okay, next week we'll continue this learned man.